3° I FREE WILL AND FOUR ENGLISH PHILOSOPHERS (HOBBES LOCK, HUME AND MILL) \ FREEWILL AND FOUR ENGLISH PHILO SOPHERS • (HOBBES, LOCKE HUME AND MILL) • BY THE REV. JOSEPH RICKABY, S.J. "The belief in freedom is at the root of our entire conception of personality " — Mallock, Rcconstruflionof Belief EX LIBRIS ST, BASIL'S SCHOLASTICATE No. BURNS & GATES I BENZIGER BROS 28 Orchard Street New York Chicago London W Cincinnati 1906 NOV1619S8 All Right, Reieri.'tJ THE PREFACE IN their original form these pages were written in the years 1871-4. Since then they have been sub mitted to much castigation and amendment, less per haps than they deserve, at the hands of the writer, then youthful, now an elderly man. This fact may account for some inequalities of style. Certain "tender memories of the past" have stayed my hand from pruning away all traces of the exuberance of youth. Meanwhile the importance of the subject has grown rather than diminished, chiefly, I think, owing to the prevalence of the Kantian philosophy. I may as well forewarn the reader that Kant is not discussed here, except indirectly, in so far as the phenomenalism of Hume may be considered to have prepared the way for Kant. I have written elsewhere: "Though men are slow to see it and loth to own it, — from reminis cences I think of the odium theologicum hanging about the question, — free will still remains the hub and centre of philosophical speculation."* In this work the subject is treated entirely on philosophical grounds: that is to say, there is no reference to grace, predesti nation, or the Fall. Thus St Augustine stands out of the controversy: so too Calvin and Jansenius. My * "Free Will in God and Man," pp. 142-155, in the Second Series of my Oxford and Cambridge Conferences, 1900-1901 : see also in my "Political and Moral Essays, 1902, an Essay on "Morality with out Free Will." vj FREE WILL method is to quote a passage from the English philo sopher under examination, and then discuss it. The method has its drawbacks, but it ensures definiteness, and seems about as fair to the philosopher discussed as any other form of procedure. It is not the writer's fault if the reader has not his Hobbes, or his Locke, or his Hume by his side, and does not read round and study in the context the extract presented to him. The faff that man has free will is far more certain, — it is a point of Catholic faith, — than any explanation /IOVP he has it. As to how free will works, the Church has given no explanation: there is much divergence even of orthodox opinion, and, wherever my reading has travelled, considerable obscurity. The fact is usually proved by the indirect method of enlarging upon the consequences of a denial of free will. That method I too have frequently employed. But further I offer some positive view of the precise working of free will. I have not borrowed it from Locke. I arrived at the view, or rather was led into it, in the year 1868; and it has satisfied my mind ever since. It will be found, however, to approximate to a view put for ward, on second thoughts, by Locke.* The view I take is briefly this. To will at all, our will must be struck by a motive, which raises in us what I have have called a "spontaneous complacency." As the four philosophers under review all agree, and I agree with them, this complacency is a fact of physical sequence, a necessity, under the circumstances. But it is not yet a volition. It does not become a volition until it is * See Extraft 8 from Locke, pp. 100-104. THE PREFACE vij hugged, embraced, enhanced, under advertence, by the conscious self. This process takes time, — I do not mean so many seconds measured by the watch, for thought time goes on other wheels than motion time, — but still it takes time. Free will turns upon the absence of any need of your making up your mind at once to accept the particular complacency thus pre sent in your soul: observe, you cannot here and now accept any other; you cannot here and now accept what is not here and now offered; you cannot just at present fling yourself upon the absent. Thus time is gained for rival motives to come up, according to the ordinary laws of association, perception, or personal intercourse: each of these motives excites its own necessary complacency, till at last some present com placency is accepted and endorsed by the person ; and that is an acl: of free will. Not to have a regressus in in- finitum, we must further observe that no volition is requisite simply to hesitate, delay, and withhold your acceptance of any present complacency, — in facl:, to re main undecided and irresolute. You may, of course, put forth a positive volition to wait and see more of the question: all I say is that such a positive volition is not indispensable; your will may hang fire without your resolving to be irresolute: which important point Locke never came clearly to remark. This explanation may not account for free will in GOD and in His holy angels; but in so difficult a matter it is much if we can form some theory which a philo sopher may debate, and a sound theologian will not bar as "heretical," "erroneous," or "temerarious." viij FREE WILL I may add that while I am much concerned that my reader should not be a determinist, I am compara tively indifferent whether he accepts my explanation of free will, or any other, or regards the process as inexplicable. J. R. Tope's Hall, Oxford, Midsummer, 1906. THE CONTENTS THOMAS HOBBES Seftion I. Doctrine of free will stated. Not every action free, nor every free action equally free. Calculability of human action (cf. Hume, Sedions III, IV; Mill, Seftions I, VIII) Page I X Seftion II. Spontaneous, Voluntary, Secondarily-automatic 7 Stflion III. Cause and condition 10 Seftisn IV. Sufficient cause 14 Seftion V. Moral character of the Deity on the necessarian hypo thesis (cf. Hume, Section XI). Predication of GOD and His creatures analogous, not univocal 1 6 Sfftion VI. Necessarian theory of punishment (cf. Mill, Sections XI, XII) 22 Seftion VII. Necessarian view of consultation. Neccssarianism re nounced in practice. Its effects on morality (cf. pp. 195, 225) 24 Seftion VIII. Praise in the absence of free will 28 Seftion IX. Hobbesian piety 31 Seftion X. Hobbesian repentance 34 Seftion XI. Hobbesian prayer 34 Seftion XII. Hobbesian definition of sin. When voluntarincss may co-exist with necessity 36 Seftion XIII. Compulsion and free will 39 Seftion XIV. Grades of free will. Freedom not to be confounded with power (cf. Locke, Sections I- 1 1 1) 43 Seftion XV. How far the will can be said to be determined by the last practical judgement 50 Seftion XVI. The abiding now of eternity (cf. Mill, Section II). The Heraclitean flux 53 Seftion XVII. Free will other than the absence of impediments to action 63 Seftion XVIII. A free volition not an entirely new move in the mind 66 Seftion XIX. Necessarianism not provable by the law of excluded middle 70 x FREE WILL JOHN LOCKE Seflion I. Free will not power to carry out what one wills Page 7 5 Seflion II. The same 77 Seflion III. The same (cf. p. zoo) 78 Seflion IV. Faculty and habit . 8 1 Seflion V. Examination of the argument that man cannot forbear willing for or against any given proposal, and therefore is not free. What is irresolution? 82 Seflion VI. Free will not a regressu; in infinitum. Restatement of the process of free will 87 Seflion VII. Is the will determined by the greatest present uneasi ness? St Augustine on the uneasiness of this present life and the peace of the life to come 90 Seflion VIII. Locke's admission in the second edition of his Essay that man's liberty lies in his power to suspend the execution and satisfaction of his desires while he examines the value of them. This suspensory power may operate negatively, without any positive volition thereto. Volition can be formed only upon present complacency 100 Seflion IX. It is not true liberty to break loose from the conduct of reason 105 Seflion X. Recapitulation of the argument with Locke 1 06 DAVID HUME Seflion I. A test of contradiction between philosophers, real or verbal (cf. p. 194) 1 15 Seflion II. Idea of necessity, whence derived. Not entirely from the uniformity of nature. It involves a consciousness of self, and a measuring of self against nature 1 1 7 Seflion III. Calculability of human actions, so far as our experience goes, not inconsistent with free will. The inference of absolute calculability rendered suspect by the fact of self-consciousness. Ferrier on the consciousness of self 125 Seflion IV. Principle of habitual volition and principle of averages together sufficiently explain the calculability of human actions, without recourse to necessarianism 133 Seflion V. Free will and personality. Root error of an impersonal psychology (cf. Mill, Seftion III) 13? Seflion VI. Necessity a quality of the agent, not of the looker-on. How is it that we are so much at fault in the prediction of our own conduct? 142 THE CONTENTS xj Seflion VII. Cause and explanation. Every free volition hasa"cause," but not an "explanation" in the technical sense (cf. Mill, Sec tions III, VIII) Page 144 Sefiion VIII. Free will and chance 150 Seflion IX. Doctrines theologically "dangerous." Necessarianism not merely dangerous, but contradictory of the Church's teaching I 5 2 Seflion X. Influence of character on conduct. A free volition emi nently a personal act 156 Sefiion XI. Theological consequences of necessarianism. Hume against Hume. Vulpine humility 159 JOHN STUART MILL Seflion I. The doctrine called Philosophical Necessity unproven by experience 165 Seflion II. Free will and divine foreknowledge 1 66 Seflion III. " Mysterious constraint," " magical spell," " mystical tie " of cause and effect, misconceptions of the phenomenalist school due to their ignoring of personality. Volition not a mere phenomenon of physical science I 70 Seflion IV. Necessity as meaning " uncounteradtableness " 178 Seflion V. Mill and the Owenite. Is a man's character formed for him or by him? 183 Seflion VI. Can we alter our character? 185 Seflion VII. Mill admits free will after all (he revokes his conces sion, p. 231 : cf. Locke, Section VIII: Hume, Section XI, for simi lar concessions. Hobbes alone never flinches, but see p. 28) 1 86 Seflion VIII. Why brute agency is necessary agency. Away from necessity, no induction possible. Calculability of human action. " Cause " and " explanation " 1 89 Seflion IX. Consciousness of free will 198 Seflion X. Are we conscious of being able to act in opposition to the strongest present desire or aversion ? (cf. pp. 53, 103) 201 Seflion XI. Utilitarian theory of punishment (cf. Hobbes, Section VI). New treatment of homicidal mania 205 Seflion XII. Retributive punishment. Connexion of sin and suffer ing, no mere subjective association. Civil punishment, how retri butive 216 Seflion XIII. List of actions good and evil unchanged by determi nism. Intellectual necessity. Brute necessity 225 Seflion XIV. Mill's final protest against fatalism. Modified fatalism. Roundabout fatalism. Determinism: fatalism in theory, not in practice 229 FREE WILL AND FOUR ENGLISH PHILOSOPHERS THOMAS HOBBES Of Liberty and Necessity : a Treatise wherein all Con troversy concerning Predestination, E/fffion, Free Will, Grace, Merits, Reprobation, etc., is fully de cided and cleared: in answer to a Treatise Writ ten by the Bishop of Londonderry on the same subject I "\ T 7HEREAS he says thus, If I be free to write V V this discourse, I have obtained the cause ; I deny that to be true, for it is enough to his freedom of writing that he had not written it, unless he would himself. ... It may be his Lordship [the Bishop] thinks it all one to say, I was free to write it, and, It was not neces sary I should write it. But I think otherwise. For he is free to do a thing, that may do it if he have the will to do it; and may forbear if he have the will to for bear. And yet if there be a necessity that he shall have the will to do it, the aclion is necessarily to follow; and if there be a necessity that he shall have the will to forbear, the forbearing also will be necessary. The question therefore is not, whether a man be a free agent, that is to say, whether he can write or forbear, speak 2 FREE WILL or be silent, according to his will; but whether the will to write and the will to forbear come upon him accord ing to his will or according to anything else in his own power, I acknowledge this Hberty^ that_I j:jUL_do. if_J.. willi .buL_tQ._say: J_ .can. will" if I wjll I take .to be an absurd speech." Hobbes considers human agency to be at once free and necessitated: free, because the action follows the will of the agent; necessitated, inasmuch as the agent, under the circumstances, could not possibly have willed otherwise than as he did will. Hobbes takes it to be an absurd speech to say I can will if 1 will. What indeed is the meaning of that phrase in the mouths of such as use it? An outline of what they mean would run thus: Upon adverting to a present affection, a like or a dislike which has risen up within me, I am often competent either to take up or not to take up that affection: if I do take it up, 1 elicit a volition or full act of my will, which is a free act inasmuch as I take up, adopt and sanction for my own an affection which I am competent not to sanction; while for my sanctioning it no reason can be given be yond the fact that I, a person, that is an intelligent nature, exerting my privilege as a person, do choose to lend myself to the affection which has come over me. An example. An opportunity offers for striking a lu crative but unjust bargain. The idea recurs of securing the gain, and my breast warms with approbetion of that idea. So far I have been the passive victim of associa tions and feelings. There has been no personal action emanating from me. I now advert to my mind's spon- THOMAS HOBBES 3 taneous and unauthorised approval of this idea. If I continue to approve of it under advertence, spontaneity passes into freedom, the movement started from with out has been sustained from within me. I have willed that which at first I felt. But perhaps I do not decide quite so readily. I let feelings and the ideas which oc casion them troop in associated trains across the stage of my consciousness. I retain none of them. Con flicting thoughts of gain and of honesty, the joys of a good bargain, the remorses of a fraud, replace one another, as past mental experience marshals their array. Whilst this process lasts, I am said to be thinking the matter over. At length my mind is made up. The idea of improving the opportunity or else the idea of letting the opportunity pass has recurred: it has given me com placency, as it gave me before, and this time I have embraced the complacency. Thereby I have done a voluntary act. I may indeed recall it, but still it is done. And the act, besides being voluntary, is free, for in it I have embraced a complacency which I need not have embraced. The above is a mere statement of doctrine, not a proof. But surely it is something to state clearly a doc trine which adversaries pronounce nonsensical. Non sense generally will not bear stating. If, then, I have presented an intelligible, definite theory, there is pre sumption of its not being nonsense. Great part of the discredit that attaches to the doc trine of free will comes from its being supposed to mean that whatever a man may do from morning to night he does everything alike freely. Nothing of the 4 FREE WILL sort. A reflective adult performs perhaps a dozen a<5tions a day that are altogether free: a child, — whether a child proper or a grown baby, — say half a dozen: call another hundred actions free more or less, and you may de scribe the rest of the man's daily course as shaped without advertence and without freedom, except such part of it as is determined by previous free acts. That part would be technically termed free in its cause. The freedom of an agent bears a direct ratio to his actual knowledge of what he is about: now as mankind know what they are about, some more, some less, some scarcely at all, and none always with an actual know ledge, it cannot be said that all the actions of men are free, or that all their free actions are equally free. Much light falls on this matter from the counsels of Christian ascetics. Let me point in passing to the splen did psychological education which the Church presses upon her children, teaching them to lead an interior life, to examine their consciences, to confess their sins not of word and deed only, but also sins of thought. These Christian spiritualists, then, warn us against doing our actions through routine and custom, telling us that we shall gain little merit by such mechanical performances. Why little merit? Because merit attaches to conscious agents, not to automata; to freedom, not to machinery. A creature of habit, working blindly in a secondarily automatic groove, may be a useful ma chine, but scarcely a virtuous man. At the same time we learn from the above-cited authorities that a gene ral pious intention not revoked suffices to impart merit to a long sequence of work gone through with- THOMAS HOBBES 5 out further advertence. This instruction clears away a difficulty that is often urged against our freedom. How, it is asked, can that human aclion be free which may be unerringly calculated beforehand to be about to occur? "When a commander orders his soldiers to wheel, to deploy, to form square, to fire a battery,"* Mr Samuel Bailey demands, "is he less confident in the result than he is when he performs some physical operation, — when he draws a sword, pulls a trigger, or seals a dispatch?" Supposing that he is equally confi dent of both results, still I say the physical result is a sheer necessity, while the moral result is due to a foregone free volition. Those soldiers declare their will once for all to wheel, deploy, form square, or fire a bat tery at the word of command. They willed when they need not have willed to undertake these manoeuvres. They may be conscripts, but they are not dummies; they took their allotted service freely. They were not brought into the ranks like sacks of stones: they came there, and no one could have foretold for certain that such and such men individually would consent to come. But once they have come, their officers calcu late upon that general intention of obedience of which the uniform is a pledge. The soldier need not will to obey for every order he executes: his initial purpose is enough, if he does not depart from it. But so to de part would require an express new volition, as obe dience is in possession. A volition, however, does not spring up without a motive. If then an officer has no ground to imagine any motive for mutiny rife amongst * Letten on the Philosophy of the Human Mind, second scries, p. 166. 6 FREE WILL his men, he relies upon their previous loyal purpose working itself out unopposed; and he feels as sure of their muscles as they of their powder. It is further to be observed that a perfect apparent good, — or in other words, a good which quite satisfies him to whom it occurs, — does not leave the will the liberty of refusing. But such a perfect good hardly ever presents itself to an adult who adverts to what he en joys. The psalmist sings, "Take delight in the LORD." Undoubtedly the LORD fills with delight the blessed souls who "see Him as He is"; but He seldom satis fies our capacity for delight, who see Him "in a glass, darkly." Therefore the delight which we consciously take in the LORD is free, and if free also meritorious. It is our present sore distress, and at the same time the condition of our merit and eternal reward, that the ability to conceive enjoyment in us vastly transcends our ability to enjoy. Take any enjoyment that you can: think of it, and your thought has outrun it; you want more. There are rare moments when some unexpected blessing received fills our heart brimming over: no thing seems wanting then to our bliss but continu ance. But the very names of rapture, transport, ecstasy applied to such states show that in these states feeling momentarily precludes reflection. We are not free in those moments: no mind is free without reflection. But when "Richard is himself again," when we reflect upon our state, forthwith we conceive something better and our liberty of choice returns. By our use of liberty we make our way to our lasting city. There we shall gaze face to face on perfect goodness, and yield for eternity THOMAS HOBBES 7 our feeling, our understanding and our will to the sweet constraints of His love. Till then "content is not the natural frame of any human mind, but is the offspring of compromise."* II "All voluntary actions, where the thing that indu- ceth the will is not fear, are called also spontaneous. . . But every spontaneous action is not therefore volun tary, for voluntary presupposes some precedent deli beration. . . His Lordship is deceived, if he think any spontaneous action, after once being checked in it, differs from an action voluntary and elective; for even the setting of a man's foot in the posture for walking, and the action of ordinary eating, was once deliberated of how and when it should be done; and though afterwards it became easy and habitual so as to be done without forethought, yet that does not hinder but that the act is voluntary and proceedeth from election." A 'voluntary action Hobbes defines to be a premed itated action: a spontaneous action he defings.tn he any ac{iont premeditated or unpremeditated, that \% not dic tated by fear. He continues: Once we have stopped over a spontaneous action, and thought in the act how we should do it, every subsequent spontaneous repe tition, besides being spontaneous, is also a premedi tated or voluntary action. Whence he concludes against the Bishop, — who had laid it down that spontaneous actions were necessary, voluntary actions free, — that an action may be spontaneous and voluntary at the same * Bain's Emotions and Will, p. 453. 8 FREE WILL time, in other words, "that necessity and election may stand together." I cannot think that Bishop Bramhall, when he called spontaneous actions necessitated actions, classed as spontaneous all actions not dictated by fear. That is Hobbes's account of the word spontaneous. But had it been the Bishop's, he would never have written against Hobbes in defence of free will, for, allowing that actions not dictated by fear were necessitated, he could not possibly pretend that actions dictated by fear were free; so that, between actions done for fear and actions not done for fear, all actions whatsoever would be done of necessity; that is, the Bishop would have agreed with Hobbes. Surely, too, it is a strange argument that habitual actions are premeditated, because the actions, which formed the habit, were premeditated. Consider the habit of dancing. A pupil curveting for the first time before a dancing-master studies every step. But to declare in consequence that, when the pupil has become an expert, every trip of his "light fantastic toe " in the ballroom is a premeditated action, — this surely is either an abuse of reason or an abuse of language. If Hobbes means by "premeditated" what ordinary Englishmen mean, namely, "done with forethought," then his con clusion does not follow from his premisses; but if he means "formerly done with forethought," he must be speaking some other language than English. 1 allow that the resolution to dance at a ball is a premed itated voluntary act, but 1 refuse to extend the appel- THOMAS HOBBES 9 lation to each step which the dancer takes. It is upon such habitual operations* that the issue raised by Hobbes turns. * Called by physiologists "secondarily automatic movements." Dr Carpenter says: "There can be no doubt that the nerve-force is disposed to pass in special tracks; and it seems probable that while some of these are originally marked out for the automatic move ments, others [i.e., the nerve-tracks of the secondarily automatic movements] may be gradually worn in, so to say, by the habitual adions of the will; and that _when a train of sequential actions pri- tjquiilj,ijjj£eckd by the will has'once bcen'FeTjnbp^erationrli may"* contimie~wi^hQut a"ny~TurTfreT mITiTp'nrp ^^JmgL-lhjil-iQJJlEga • • An Tndwdual who is subject to 'absence of mind,' may fall into a reverie whilst walking in the streets; his attention may be entirely absorbed in a train of thought, and he may be utterly unconscious of any interruption in its continuity; and yet during the whole of that time his limbs shall have been in motion, carrying him along the accustomed path. . . It has been maintained by some metaphysi cians and physiologists, that these 'secondarily automatic' movements always continue to be voluntary, because their performance is origi nally due to a succession of volitional acts, and because, in any par ticular case, it is the will which first excites them, whilst an exertion ivfll *f ryf^ tp ^ihcck thyn at any time. But this doctrine m- thr nntinn that thr will ia ift.a.slaie_j3f j^nauIum-Tila: oscjl/ Xjor^bctwecn the train of thought and^ the train of movement; whereaTriothing TjTnnrq cgrjtajnjto the individual who is the su¥ject ^f both, than that the former may HP as nnintrrriipjed _asjf the bpd^ were perfectly at rest, and his reverie were taking place in the quie- tude of hit own study. Amj_a£it commonly happens that, the direction .taken is that in whiclTtlie individual is most in the habit of walking. Jj^ will not unfrcquently occur that if he had previously intended" tojxirsuc soffiti firhprj-hp fimli himttlf, irhi" hl" -—'—"^ --: "«• •"•' ""^ in a locality which may be very remote from that towards which Kia^walk was originally destined; whicji_would not be the case if hjJLJJlcni^mcnts had been still under the purposive direction ot tKe >yj]lv^mj_al though^ it js^jjejrjeflly: true that these movements can^ ^ht^at_jny \\mcL. fcitu'cked by an~oHu7t 'of IIul!Zsgttr}>e]^'rhi?'docslibt realj^_Midicatc__that_the will has been previously engaged in sustain- ing_Lhem; since, for tKe wTTI to act upon them"at" all, the io FREE WILL Hobbes has used his own terminology, and not his adversary's. I crave permission to do likewise. By ^spon taneous acl: of the will, then, I understand the compla cency which arises from the apprehension of good, previous to advertence. This spontaneous act is a necessary act. By a voluntary act I understand the ad hesion with advertence to a complacency. That act of complacency, from being spontaneous, becomes volun tary by being consciously adhered to. If the complacency does not quite satisfy him who is the subject of it, and yet he adheres to it, then his voluntary act is free, he adheres where he need not. But if the complacency under advertence does quite satisfy him, he cannot but adhere; his adhesion then is an act at once voluntary and necessary. Therefore voluntariness and necessity may stand together, as Hobbes argued they might. But it does not follow that they commonly do stand toge ther in this world. Ill "That which I say necessitateth and determina- teth every action, is the sum of all things, which being now existent, conduce and concur to the production of that action hereafter, whereof if any one thing now were wanting, the effect could not be produced." A special interest attaches to this extract: for if we read phenomena in place of things, and infallibly deter- _must be recalled to thgm^Qd_llie^ejebjrumaniisl-b£j1Lberated.iram itsjDrevious self-occupation." The same authority terms the forma- tion~bf~a secondarily TuToTTTaTic habitT"" the gradual conversion of a vbliHoriaHnto an '"automatic' train of movements7so"tharaTlast this £rain, once started, shall continue to run down~of'itselt."— "pks of Human PAyfie/o^y~p^r^2, 610, seventh edition. THOMAS HOBBES n minateth for necessitated and determinateth^ those slight amendments will bring Hobbes exactly to express a view very generally taken at the present day regarding causation both physical and mental. For an instance of physical causation we will con sider the orbit of the earth. I will enumerate "the sum of all things which being now existent conduce and con cur to the production of that action, whereof if any one thing now were wanting, the effect could not be pro duced." There are the sun and the remaining planets; item, the distance of the earth from each of the other planets and from the sun; item, the tangential velocity of the earth; item, the respective masses of earth, sun and planets; item, the absence of further perturbatory influences, such as would arise from the introduction of a new member into the solar system. Were any part of this enumeration left out, and no compensation given, "the effect could not be produced," i.e., the earth would not then describe the path which it does describe under its present data.* * The absence of influences thit might have been present in a particular case, but are not, need not be specified in the Hobbesian view. All history being an unbroken chain of consequent following antecedent, — "necessarily," according to Hobbes, "uniformly," ac cording to Mill, — pure possibility, or "that which might be but never shall," becomes a name of nothing. "Every act which is pos sible shall at some time be produced" (Hobbes, First Grounds of Philosophy, chap. ix). Therefore to talk of what might have been. how, for instance, an_effcri; whit-h h.i< followed frpmone cause might liavc followed from another, " I take to be an absurd speech." To The best ofj from another ^ans"; but now that it hat fnllnwed from this, WJG Know thafcould not have followed from aught else. Modern Nomi- nalists^perceiving that \$ could means did, then could not means did not, 12 FREE WILL The older philosophers would distinguish among the enumerated determinants of the orbit aforesaid. The attracting bodies they would style the "causes," but the disposition of those bodies in space, along with the absence of perturbation, they would style the " condi tions " of the particular effect observable in that orbit. And they would define cause, "the thing which acts"; and conditions, "the circumstances under which a cause acts." The modern school, however, of which Hobbes was a forerunner, applies the name condition to " each of the things which produce and concur to the produc tion of that action," and denominates the "sum" of those things the "cause" of the action or effect pro duced. "The cause," says Mill,* "is the sum total of the conditions, positive and negative, taken together." If one of these conditions were wanting, and were not otherwise supplied, the effect could not be produced. Their "sum," in Hobbesian phrase, "necessitated and determinateth" the effect. Mill, eschewing all men tion of necessity, would say, "Their sum causes the effect"; meaning, "they are the set of antecedents, have struck. OH J af..tllcuiphJlQspp]iicaljocabukr^the superfLuaus,ex- pressipns, can, £^M^MJj^ti must, power, possiFUtty^necfsiit^ This can celling of~terms alone differentiates the "uniformist" from the "necessarian," John Stuart Mill from Thomas Hobbes. Under this caveat we must read the phrase, "plurality of causes," where it__ jOjxjjjS-Jn-M444-V wri tinge; nofr-that ono-a»H the samr f:ftrcLcauld fojjc)\\^jwjiollj_f'rom each of many causes, butjhat like eft'ccts^have followed from many causes ; whence the inadmissibllity oFthe~K1-ir&. arKurncnt From effect to caJHsCj. r~subloin this note because I wish to "sliovv how little ultimate difference there is between Hobbes and the modern thinkers with whom I am about to compare him. * Logic, bk in, chap, v, § 3. THOMAS HOBBES 13 positive and negative, upon which the consequent invariably follows without further condition." For moral causation let us revert to our example of a man being tempted to strike a bargain, advantageous but unjust. Suppose he yields. Let us sift out and dis tinguish cause and condition in that free act. The_cjiuse of the volition is the man _himsgjfLH£i^Uva, was derived by the old etymologists from /uept'£w, I divide, because, as Terence says, curce dfaersum trahunt. 56 FREE WILL happiness where the heart is at rest. Of that type will be the eternal bliss of the saints. Face to face with the Object of their beatitude, and absorbed in the contem plation of the same, they will take even less note of time than the hermit in the legend: the everlasting years will roll on, measured by the motion of matter; but the thought, life and existence of the elect will remain a point, a nunc stans^ an ever-abiding now, in the vision of GOD.* To the same purpose St Augustine writes: "It has seemed to me that time is nothing but a lengthening out of what I know not; but I should be surprised if *The relativity of time to the thinking mind is brought out in the following extract from Newman's 'Dream ofGerontius. The soul just departed wonders at not being immediately confronted with its Judge. The Guardian Angel accounts for the delay: For spirits and men by different standards mete The less and greater in the flow of time. By sun and moon, primeval ordinances, — By stars which rise and set harmoniously, — By the recurring seasons and the swing, This way and that, of the suspended rod, Precise and punctual, men divide their hours, Equal, continuous, for their common use. Not so with us in th' immaterial world; But intervals in their succession Are measured by the living thought alone, And grow or wane with its intensity. And time is not a common property; But what is long is short, and swift is slow, And near is distant, as received and grasped By this mind and by that; and every one Is standard of his own chronology; And memory lacks its natural resting points Of years and centuries and periods. It is thy very energy of thought Which keeps thcc from thy GOD. THOMAS HOBBES 57 it were not a lengthening out of the mind itself."* "In thee, my mind, I measure periods of time. . . In thee, 1 say, the impression which passing things make upon thee endures even after they are past. What I measure is that present impression, not the things which have passed to cause it. That is what I measure when I measure periods of time. Therefore the periods of time are either that or nothing."f The holy doctor remarks that the mind fixed on GOD is "not distended but intent. "£ The mind in that case is not in time, if time is "a distension of the mind." If the spirits who contemplate GOD are unmindful of succession, because they experience no change, much more will GOD Himself be changeless and without suc cession in His knowledge. Immutability enters into the essential concept of Deity. GOD is a self-existent Being. The selfr-existent cannot be material: matter without mind to support it is, in these days, a demonstrated absurdity. The Deity, therefore, is intelligent. And if intelligent, He knows Himself. Likewise He is the fountain of all possible existence. For possible exis tences are possible contingences, and the contingent must originate from the necessary, that is, from the self-existent, which is GOD alone. Were there two self- existents, there would be two orders of possibility, two regions of intellect, two truths. Since GOD is the intel ligent origin of whatever can exist, He knows Himself and all things adlual and possible in Himself. His knowledge, being thus infinite, must be unchanging: a change would be the introduction of a limit. GOD'S * Con/, xi, c. xxvi. f Ibid. c. xxvii. I c. xxix. 58 FREE WILL mind, therefore, never changes. But, as we saw before, to a mind without change there is no time. Therefore there is no time to GOD. Yet GOD is eternal, as Hobbes confesses. Therefore the eternity of GOD is not an ever lasting succession.* Nay, succession would be impossible without some being that was not successive. Let us consider a human being running his course year by year. He is alwaysgrow- ing older : he is always the same person : nay, he could not * " // alone in correct parlance belongs to the eternal Essence : was and shall be are expressions proper for creation that passes in time: for past and future are two states of transition, while that which is ever unswervingly the selfsame is like to become neither older nor younger by time, nor ever to have been created, nor to be now a creature, nor destined to be hereafter; and in a word it stoops not to undergo any of the alterations which creation has attached to the things that fleet before sense." — Plato, Tim." According to Heraclitus there is no more permanence about sub stances and persons than about the rate of a falling stone or the tints of a sunset; all things are in a flux and nothing endures. 62 FREE WILL infinitely multiplied sets of changes simultaneously going on in worlds too numerous to count, dispersed through a space that baffles imagination?"* How indeed, if really I be myself nothing but a flux of states of consciousness? But it is not only GOD, His eternity and existence, that vanish under the analysis of Heraclitus; we and the objects of our experience equally disappear. We are always becoming older. But if nothing is permanent in us, it is not we that become older: the term we is inept. We do not become anything, and, according to Heraclitus, we are not anything. There is an end of us; an end also of what we experience, for nothingness can experience nothing. So one might improve upon the Heraclitean formula, and instead of "all things are in a flux " (TTIIVTO. pi) read "all things have vanished" (irdvTa. E/O/OH), or with Napoleon flying from Waterloo, Tout est perdu. Such is the evil end to which a philosophy comes which has made a bad start. The starting point of philo sophy, and indeed of thought, is the fact of conscious ness, I am. Thence our thought flies to beings distinct from ourselves, and to a being of beings, which is GOD, Speculative thinkers have dwelt upon the notion of being to the undue neglect of the I who am. They have ignored their own personality, and the personality of their Creator, to glorify an abstraction. Then the ab straction has been discovered to be an abstraction, and flung aside accordingly, without concern for its founda- * Herbert Spencer in Contemporary Review for June, 1 872, p. 151. A series of states of consciousness could not work the universe; but such a series is not GOD. See St Thomas, Summa contra Gentiles, i, ch. liv. THOMAS HOBBES 63 tion in f;ict. Being has yielded to becoming. But the forgotten ego cries out against the usurpation both of beingand becoming. Heracliteans are ever talkingabout themselves, and thereby giving the lie to their own im personal teachings. When will these philosophers retrace their steps and start afresh from the practice of the Delphic counsel, "Know thyself"? Man's self is a noble object to study for its own sake; yet not for that sake would the counsel be worthy to be inscribed on a tem ple. An inscription fit for a holy place should contain a revelation of GOD. "Know thyself "contains that reve lation: it induces knowledge of GOD. Psychology forms the groundwork of natural theology. XVII " Liberty is the absence of all the impediments to action that are not contained in the nature and intrin- sical quality of the agent; as, for example, the water is said to descend freely, or to have liberty to descend by the channel of the river, because there is no impedi ment that way, but not across, because the banks are impediments. And though the water cannot ascend, yet men never say it wants the liberty to ascend, but the faculty or power, because the impediment is in the nature of the water and intrinsical. So also we say, he that is tied wants the liberty to go, because the impediment is not in him, but in his bands; whereas we say not so of him that is sick or lame, because the impediment is in himself." Free will goes further than this. "The nature and intrinsical quality of the agent" determines his spon taneous attitude to any motive that is applied to him: it does not determine him to identity himself with that 64 FREE WILL motive upon advertence, and make it his own by con sent and acceptance. He so consents, if he does con sent, that under the same collocation of motives, with the same character and antecedents, and under the same spontaneously determined attitude of will, he might still have held back his consent and not made up his mind to anything. The alternative for the moment, I observe once more, is not between consent and positive rejec tion: that would be "liberty of contrariety," and free will does not go so far. The alternative is between con sent and the mere negative attitude of a mind not yet made up; between volition x and zero of volition: that is properly called "liberty of contradiction," and in "liberty of contradiction" human free will essentially consists. Evidently, this is more than "liberty from constraint," which is the utmost liberty that Hobbes and other determinists concede. Some of them are pleased to call it "self-determination," but their " self- determination" is not free will. These "self-determi- nists" are as good determinists, and as true necessa rians, as Thomas Hobbes himself, only less outspoken. Metaphorically, we say that the water flows freely in a river when it appears to flow according to its own choice, seeking its level as man seeks his good. We say that an untethered mare is free to run away, be cause she is left to her own proclivities. In a word, we call all those things free which are allowed to behave according to their natures. What then? Does it follow that a London citizen is not free in any higher sense than that in which a horse at grass, or the water of the Thames, is free? Hardly, unless it appear that the water THOMAS HOBBES 65 and the horse are man's natural equals. But if huma nity rises superior over bestiality and water-power, it may be expected that the citizen, following his nature, shall be free in one way; and Bucephalus and the Thames, following their respective natures, shall be free in their own way, but not in his. According to Hobbes, they are all free in the same way. He sapi- ently explains how the river is free, and concludes that man can have no other freedom. Man's nature is neither purely material, nor purely animal, nor purely intellectual, but a compound of the three. A material nature moves whither it is drawn or thrust without feeling the motion, particle supplanting particle by mere material laws: an animal nature makes for pleasurable feelings and avoids painful feelings, real or imaginary; it is ruled by those feelings as a needle by a magnet. Various functions of man's organic life are discharged by animal appliances, when higher direc tive powers are in abeyance. An intellectual nature essentially knows itself. It is ruled by perfect good, according to the highest conception which it has framed of good. When man reflects what he is about, he occu pies an intellectual position. Finding himself realising what is to him a thoroughly adequate and satisfactory good, he must will that object. But finding a good in adequate and unsatisfactory, he may hold back his volition. It is not in any nature to be ruled by what fails to content it. The swine devours its acorns per force, for it has no sense of better things, and the acorns yield perforce to be crunched by the swine, for they have no sense at all. But man takes his food freely: he 5 66 FREE WILL has visions of what he prefers to meat and drink. An anomaly here appears to obtain that, while brute matter and brute beasts are guided in their behaviour by ade quate objects, man alone is left to act upon inadequate grounds. But we must remember that man, too, has his adequate Object, — only out of reach for the present life. XVIII "I conceive that nothing taketh beginning from itself, but from the action of some other immediate agent without itself; and that therefore, when first a man hath an appetite or will to something, to which immediately before he had no appetite nor will, the cause of his will is not the will itself, but something else not in his own disposing." The meaning here is that all change is produced, not by the subject of the change, but by some being external to the subject. The assertion is true, and borne out by enumeration of instances. Thus an element of matter is moved, not by any self-moving agency,— for it is inert, — but by the agency of another element. And man's mind, it seems to me, never directly induces upon itself a modification entirely new. I agree that, "when first a man hath an appetite or will to some thing, to which immediately before he had no appetite nor will, the cause of his will [in that first stage of volition] is not the will itself, but something else not in his own disposing." What I have denominated "spontaneous complacency," results in the mind with out the person's authorship: it arises either through a sensation, as when one catches sight of a beautiful ob ject; or through an association, as when the [pre- THOMAS HOBBES 67 established connexion of thoughts brings up the idea of the destruction of an enemy. Such a complacency in me is not mine: I have neither summoned nor sanctioned it, although I may be to some extent re sponsible for its coming, inasmuch as my previous acts, or my present negligence, may have facilitated its access to me. I can exercise no act properly my own, no act, that is to say, of free will, without an antece dent act which is not properly my own, namely, an act of spontaneous complacency. For a free volition is a sustaining of a complacency spontaneously arisen, after advertence to the insufficiency of the same. And this distinction, between the spontaneous and the re flex act of the will, annuls Hobbes's conclusion here drawn, "that voluntary actions have all of them neces sary causes"; for spontaneous volitions are traceable to necessary causes, but reflex volitions ordinarily are not. XIX " I hold that to be a sufficient cause, to which no thing is wanting that is needful to the producing of the effect. The same also is a necessary cause. For if it be possible that a sufficient cause shall not bring forth the effect, then there wanteth somewhat which was needful to the producing of it, and so the cause was not sufficient. . . That ordinary definition of a free agent, namely, that a free agent is that which, when all things are present which are needful to produce the effect, can nevertheless not produce it, implies a contradiction that is nonsense; being as much as to say the cause may be sufficient, that is to say necessary, and yet the effect shall not follow. . . That there is no such thing as an agent, which when all things requi- 68 FREE WILL site to action are present, can nevertheless forbear to produce it; or, which is all one, that there is no such thing as freedom from necessity, is easily inferred from that which hath been before alleged. For if it be an agent, it can work; and if it work, there is nothing wanting of what is requisite to produce the action, and consequently the cause of the action is sufficient; and if sufficient, then also necessary, as hath been proved before." Wherever there is a cause sufficient, in the Hob- besian sense of the term sufficient^ for a necessary effect, there the cause is necessary and the effect will neces sarily ensue. All effects of matter acting upon matter are necessary effects. Wherever then material sub stances are found in collocation, there is necessarily wrought a determination towards movement, the effect of the action of matter on matter. But given a cause insufficient for a necessary effect, not even Hobbes would say that that cause was necessary, or that the effect was necessarily to follow. Now, in the human mind, a motion of complacency may possibly arise, which, being adverted to, will be necessarily sustained. That is the case where the object appears to the sub ject in the light of a perfect good. There we see a necessary volition complete. But suppose the object of the complacency, when examined, appears to be not without its drawbacks. Such an object is not a sufficient cause of a necessary volition. Man's will is above be ing necessitated by what does not satisfy his desire. Consequently no necessary volition will follow the ap prehension of that object. If a volition does follow, it will be not necessitated but free. There is sufficient THOMAS HOBBES 69 cause for a free volition, but not sufficient cause for a necessary volition. At that rate, Hobbes would contend, no volition could follow at all. I am unable to agree with him there. The object of man's will is good. Perfect good he must love; imperfect good he may love. His necessary ad hesion to the former does not cut him off from freely adhering to the latter. It is natural for him to love good in any shape, although not with a necessary love, except the good which he apprehends to be perfect. Let us contemplate the case of a mother with her child. Supremely dear he is to her heart. For his sake she loves what is connected with him, — his playmates, his playthings, clothes, pictures and familiar haunts, — all that is like him, and all that he is fond of. I have little doubt that her love for her son is necessitated. She cannot choose but love him. She cannot possibly will to do him an injury. But the things which she loves for his sake she regards with an inferior affection. She might find it in her heart to burn his likeness, though she could not allow the sun's rays to beat fierce on his head. The necessity under which she lies of loving him leads to a secondary love for what relates to him, which secondary affection, however, does not possess the cogency wherewith the primary love is endowed. We must not forget that a free volition is not an entirely new move in the mind. Some motion towards the thing willed there was already, and that of neces sity: the conscious acceptance and confirmation of that motion transforms it from necessary to free. Now I maintain as a notorious fact of consciousness, upon 70 FREE WILL which no necessarian has ever thrown a doubt, that we are able advertently to make up our minds to an arrange ment wherewith we are not altogether pleased. We subscribe our Le Roi le veut, though intelligence, the the king within us, conceives, and desire yearns after, a better measure than that. We then will without a sufficient cause for a necessary volition. There ^anteth somewhat which was needful to the production of it. There fore no necessary volition is produced; but the volition, which is produced, is free. XX "It is necessary that to-morrow it shall rain or not rain. If therefore it be not necessary it shall rain, it is necessary it shall not rain, otherwise there is no necessity that the proposition, it shall rain or not rain, should be true. I know there be some that say, it may necessarily be true that one of the two shall come to pass, but not singly, that it shall rain, or that it shall not rain, which is as much as to say, one of them is necessary, yet neither of them is necessary; and there fore to seem to avoid that absurdity, they make a dis tinction, that neither of them is true determinate, but indeterminate; which distinction either signifies no more but this, one of them is true, but we know not which, and so the necessity remains, though we know it not; or if the meaning of the distinction be not that, it hath no meaning, and they might as well have said, one of them is true tityrice, but neither of them tupa- tulice"* The handling this argument is simply an exercise in formal logic. If we consider what manner of asser- *Tityre, tu patuli recubans sub tegmine fagi. — 1)irgi/, Eclogue I. THOMAS HOBBES 71 tion a disjunctive proposition makes, we shall easily perceive that no proof of necessarianism can be ex tracted out of the law of excluded middle, — that every thing necessarily either is or is not. Since the operations of inanimate nature, so far as that nature is concerned, are acknowledged on all hands to be necessary, I will alter the example to this: "It is necessary that to morrow Philip shall sin or not sin." If Hobbes can show that sin in Philip, supposed to be alive and in the exercise of his faculties to-morrow, is either a ne cessity or an impossibility, he has gained the cause. Logically examined, the disjunctive proposition, "To-morrow Philip must either sin or not sin," is tantamount to these two: (i) the assertion of Philip's sinning to-morrow necessarily involves the denial of his not sinning; (2) the denial of Philip's not sinning to-morrow necessarily involves the assertion of his sinning. If Hobbes, out of these two propositions, can gather the conclusion that "if it be not necessary Philip shall sin, it is necessary he shall not sin," he is welcome to his victory. But he does not gather that conclusion out of those two propositions, but out of the two following, into which he virtually analyses the disjunctive, "To-morrow, Philip must either sin or not sin": (i) the assertion of Philip's sinning to-mor row involves the denial of his not necessarily sinning; (2) the denial of Philip's sinning to-morrow involves the assertion of his necessarily not sinning. No logician can admit that this second pair of propositions contain formally the same statements as 72 FREE WILL the first pair. Nor will the adequacy of the first ana lysis be questioned by any one acquainted with formal logic. Therefore the second analysis is incorrect, and the attempt of Hobbes to draw a proof of necessari- anism out of the formal law of excluded middle is a pronounced failure. The two members of a disjunctive proposition are like two balls flung into the air, with a string connec ting them. Each ball is fastened, and yet both balls are loose. Each member of the disjunction is declared ne cessary, hypothetically upon the denial of the other; yet neither member is vouched for as being tethered with an absolute necessity. This must be, if that is not; and that, if this is not. We do not say: This must be, simply: nor, That must be, simply. The disjunctive form is no evidence for or against the absolute necessity of either member of the disjunction. Hobbes's argument is per haps confuted more plainly by this similitude of the two balls tied together, than by the distinction of de terminate 'and indeterminate, or even ffynfiand tupatulice. JOHN LOCKE JOHN LOCKE An Essay concerning Human Understanding Book II, Chap. XXL Of Power I far as a man has power to think or not to think, to move or not to move, according to the prefer ence or direction of his own mind, so far is a man free." It is characteristic of Locke as a writer to refuse to acknowledge difficulties. Where other philosophers check their pace, and tread warily, and whisper in one another's ear that they are drawing nigh to a very grave question, Locke flies forward with a bound, and overpowers the question, and beats it down low, and lays the answer open, as he declares, to any ordinary understanding. This procedure has its advantages. Difficulties in metaphysics, as in government, in trade or in travel, are often creatures of the imagination. The remedy in such cases is to act and cease to ima gine. Still there are difficulties, real difficulties, on every line. To ignore them is not to surmount them, but to bequeath them to posterity. When Locke sought to silence the strife about the real essences of substan ces by proclaiming them unknowable, he left it for Berkeley and Hume in the next generation to ask whether substance had any real essence at all. So the award just pronounced by him on the question of free 76 FREE WILL will is plain and intelligible; but I fear it is also irrele vant and superficial, and quite fails to touch the point at issue. The strife between necessarians and libertarians precisely concerns that preference or direction of his own mind, which Locke assumes. How does the mind prefer thinking of a thing to not thinking of it ? How does the mind direct movement rather than rest ? Does it prefer or direct in such a way as that it could not possibly prefer or direct otherwise? This is the ques tion to which necessarians answer yes, and libertarians no; and which Locke's definition of freedom touches not at all. In proof of the insufficiency of the definition, let me show that it applies to cases of the most rigid necessity. A clock is in no sense a free agent. Yet a clock might be called free when it has power to move or not to move, according to the preference and direction of its own workings. It would then be free from all extra neous, all "anti-horological" interference, such as that of a child gluing the fingers to the dial or playing with the weights. Locke, I know, speaks, not of the work ings of a machine, but of the direction of a man's own mind; and he refuses, rightly enough, to recognise any liberty away from mind. But is not this the point in dispute, whether our minds are wound up like clocks, to prefer and direct us to certain motions, or whether, they have a command over themselves, placed in them selves alone, which machines have not ? If the latter is the true idea of freedom, Locke's definition fails to convey it. JOHN LOCKE 77 II " Wherever any performance or forbearance are not equally in a man's power; wherever doing or not doing will not follow equally upon the preference of his mind directing it, there he is not free, though perhaps the action may be voluntary. . . Suppose a man to be car ried, whilst fast asleep, into a room, where is a person he longs to see and speak with, and be there locked fast in, beyond his power to get out; he awakes, and is glad to find himself in so desirable company, which he stays willingly in, i.e., prefers his stay to going away. I ask, is not this stay voluntary? I think nobody will doubt it; and yet, being locked fast in, 'tis evident he is not at liberty not to stay; he has not freedom to be gone." Let me too cite an imaginary instance. Suppose a man's mark to be required to a paper in order to the perpetration of a fraud, and another seizes his hand, and by overpowering constraint traces with it the mark re quired; and the man whose hand is held, though he cannot help himself, makes the mark with a hearty good will. I ask, is not the man thus constrained a defrauder? I do not mean a defrauder before the law, for the law takes cognisance only of the outward act, which is here evidently constrained, but a defrauder in conscience and before heaven? I think nobody will doubt it; and yet, his hand being held, it is evident that he is not at liberty not to make the mark, he has not freedom to withhold it. How then is his action wrong, if he does it not freely? It is not so much the action as the act that is wrong. The physical action of marking the paper must be performed by him whether he will or no, and none 78 FREE WILL can blame him for that his hand is forced; but the mental act by which he approves of the marking is an approval which he might have withheld, which he freely bestows, and for which GOD holds him culpable. The man who affixes his mark under such circumstances is at once a voluntary agent, and a free agent, and a guilty agent; voluntary, because he wills what he does; free, because he need not have willed it; and guilty, because he freely wills to do a fraudulent thing. Ill " If this be so, as I imagine it is, I leave it to be con sidered whether it may not help to put an end to that long agitated, and, I think, unreasonable because unin telligible question, viz., whether man's will be free or no. For if I mistake not, it follows, from what I have said, that the question itself is altogether improper; and it is as insignificant to ask whether man's will be free, as to ask whether his sleep be swift, or his virtue square; liberty being as little applicable to the will as swiftness of motion is to sleep, or squareness to virtue. Every one would laugh at the absurdity of sucha question as either of these, because it is obvious that the modifications of motion belong not to sleep, nor the difference of figure to virtue. And when any one well considers it, I think he will plainly perceive that liberty, which is but a power, belongs only to agents and cannot be an attri bute or modification of the will, which is also but a power. . . For can it be denied that whatever agent has a power to think on its own actions, and to prefer their doing or omission, either to other, has that faculty called will? Will then is nothing but such a power. Liberty, on the other hand, is the power a man has to do or forbear doing any particular action, according as JOHN LOCKE 79 its doing or forbearance has the actual preference in the mind, which is the same thing as to say, according as he himself wills it." A rambler in a hilly country will come sometimes upon a sheet of water, sombre, still and solemn, which partly from its own appearance, and partly from the ideas of size impressed by the heights around, he will judge to be very deep. He tries the experiment of going into it, and finds it a shallow with a bottom of black mud. And so the reader of Locke's great work, when he arrives at the striking passage just quoted, a passage that marks an epoch in the free will controversy, is seized with awe, and doubts not, as well from the reputation of the author as from the originality of the statement, that the reasoning which underlies it must be profound indeed. But when the first surprise is over, if he coolly proceeds to reduce the wondrous argumentation into form, another wonder will start up, how the shallow sense therein contained can have passed with so many readers for deep discernment. Locke's definitions of will and freedom may be given as follows: Will is power of thinking on one's own actions, and preferring their doing to their omission, or their omis sion to their doing. Liberty is power of doing or forbearing to do any action, according as its doing or forbearance has the actual preference in the mind. Which definitions amount to these: Will is power of choosing. Liberty is power of acting according to choice. 8o FREE WILL From which definitions it follows that this proposition, The will has freedom (or) The will is free, is equipollent with this: The power of choosing has the power of acting ac cording to choice. But that proposition is absurd, since one power cannot have another power. Therefore the proposition, "The will is free," is absurd, unintelligible, meaningless and ir relevant, or, as Locke says, insignificant and improper. This is Locke's line of argument, and no one can deny that the conclusion of it does follow from the premisses, which are definitions. But as one definition is wrong and the others defective, the whole argument must be said decidedly to halt. These are the definitions that I would substitute for them. Will is power of consciously rejecting evil and choosing good. Freedom is the not being under constraint to reject any but sheer evil, or choose any but sheer good. So that the proposition, "The will is free," means: The power of consciously rejecting evil and choosing good is not under constraint to reject any but sheer evil, or to choose any but sheer good. There is sense, I contend, in this proposition, whether it be true or not. Therefore I demand that to the proposition, "The will is free," there be restored that intelligibility, sig nificance and relevance which Locke has unwarrantably denied to it. Free will is a power, the same power as the will, as JOHN LOCKE 8 1 St Thomas shows,* but the liberty or freedom of the will is not a power but an incident of a power: it is annexed to the condition under which the power of rejecting evil and choosing good is exercised; which condition is this, that sheer good must not be rejected, nor sheer evil chosen. Sheer good to a person is that which thoroughly meets the requirements of his nature; and sheer evil that which meets those requirements in no way whatever. But the objects with which the human will is ordinarily conversant are neither sheer good nor sheer evil: they are good and evil mixed: they partly satisfy us and partly not. In the not being tied fast to such objects of choice that liberty consists which is incident to the faculty or power called the human will. IV "We may as properly say that 'tis the singing fa culty sings, and the dancing faculty dances, as that the will chooses, or that the understanding conceives. ... I think the question is not proper whether the will be free, but whether a man be free." Is not the question, 'whether a man be free to will' ? Instead of debating that, Locke inquires whether a man be free to do what he wills. For, he asks, how can we think any one freer than to have the power to do what he will ? Of course it is the man himself that sings with his singing faculty, dances with his dancing faculty, chooses with his will, and conceives with his understanding. Still we rightly say that the will chooses and the un derstanding conceives, while we do not say that the * Sum. Theol. I, q. Ixxxiii, artt. 2 and 4. 6 82 FREE WILL singing faculty sings, or that the dancingfaculty dances. The reason is not far to seek. Will and understanding are faculties, answering to the Aristotelian SvvapiQ : they are primitive powers. But dancing and singing are not * faculties,' as Locke is pleased to call them, but habits, the Aristotelian t'&g: they are acquisitions of skill. Faculty is more intimate to man than habit; and therefore, putting the part for the whole, we take that part for the whole which is more representative of the whole; and speak of the faculty doing what the man does with the faculty. V " It passes for a good plea, that a man is not free at all, if he be not as free to will, as he is to act what he wills. Concerning a man's liberty, there is yet raised this farther question, whether a man be free to will; which, I think, is what is meant when it is disputed, whether the will be free. And as to that, I imagine that, willing or volition being an action, and freedom consisting in a power of acting or not acting, a man in respect of willing or the act of volition, when any action in his power is once proposed to his thoughts, as presently to be done, cannot be free. The reason whereof is very manifest : for, it being unavoidable that the action depending on his will should exist or not exist; and its existence or not existence following perfectly the determination and preference of his will; he cannot avoid willing the existence or not exis tence of that action. It is absolutely necessary that he will the one or the other, i.e., prefer the one to the other; since one of them must necessarily follow, and that which does follow follows by the choice and de termination of his mind, that is, by his willing it: for JOHN LOCKE 83 if he did not will it, it would not be. So that, in res pect of the ad of willing, a man in such a case is not free: liberty consisting in a power to act or not to ad, which, in regard of volition, a man upon such a proposal has not. For it is unavoidably necessary to prefer the doing or forbearance of an action in a man's power, which is once so proposed to his thoughts: a man must necessarily will the one or the other of them, upon which preference or volition, the action, or its forbearance, certainly follows, and is truly voluntary; but the act of volition, or preferring one of the two, being that which he cannot avoid, a man in respect of that act of willing is under a necessity, and so cannot be free; unless necessity and freedom can consist together, and a man can be free and bound at once. This then is evident, that in all proposals of present action a man is not at liberty to will or not to will, because he cannot forbear willing: liberty con sisting in a power to act or to forbear acting, and in that only." At last Locke stands at bay before the real question, and dispatches it with a reason which he calls l>ery mani fest^ but which to me appears very obscure, and, on inspection, very inconclusive. I subjoin an analysis, which anyone may compare with the text. Three argu ments are given, or rather, three confused statements of one argument: that being Locke's custom when he feels that he has not quite hit the nail on the head, to hammer all about the spot. First Argument i. Every action dependent on a man's will must either take place or not take place. 84 FREE WILL 2. Every action dependent on a man's will takes place on condition that he wills it, and does not take place on condition that he does not will it. 3. Therefore the man must will that the action should take place, or will that it should not take place. Second Argument 1. Every action dependent on a man's will takes place by his willing it: for if he did not will it, it would not be. 2. But he must will one way or the other. 3. Therefore, one way or the other, he wills of necessity. Third Argument 1. He who cannot forbear willing is not at liberty to will or not to will. 2. Man cannot forbear willing, upon any proposal of present action. 3. Therefore man is not at liberty to will or not to will upon any proposal of present action. The first remark that I have to make upon these arguments is that they need lengthening out in order to reach the heart of the matter of free will. If they are valid, they prove that, when an action is proposed to us, we must either positively consent or positively refuse to do it: we are not free to abstain alike from consent and refusal. But some, I suppose, contend that this conclusion still leaves us free; since, though we must exert an act of the will, it rests with us, they say, to make that act a consent or a refusal. Though I do not agree with those thinkers, their position, it seems to JOHN LOCKE 85 me, has enough show of reason to render Locke's tri umph incomplete until it is rebutted. But I deny that conclusion (that we are not free to abstain alike from consent and refusal), and challenge the arguments alleged on its behalf. _ In the first argument the first proposition is true by virtue of what logicians call the law of excluded middle. The first half of the second proposition is true by the wording. The second half of that same proposition is true as it stands: it is true that the condition for an action, dependent on a man's will, not to take place, is that he shall not will it to take place. But it is not true that the condition for the action not to take place is that he shall positively will its not taking place. That is what Locke wishes to be understood in the second half of this seemingly self-evident second proposition. And that is the false conclusion which he gathers, with a therefore prefixed, in the third proposition. Surely, there is a difference between the negative state of not willing and the positive act, I will not. There is a difference between not saying yes and saying no. There is a difference between not voting for a measure and voting against it. When an action depends on my willing it, that is, making up my mind that it shall be done, my refraining from having any will, or making up my mind at all upon the matter, is quite enough to bar the action. I need not say, // shall not be; it will not be unless I say, It shall. Otherwise there would be no such thing in the world as irresolution. A man who did not at once resolve on one course would thereby have resolved on the other. Yet, who has not been ir- 86 FREE WILL resolute, undecided, unable to make up his mind, a prey to hesitation and doubt, in many a critical hour of his life? It may be replied, however, that this state of doubt consists, not in a withholding of the will, which Locke argues to be impossible, but in a quick succes sion of contradictory volitions. Is irresolution a state of rest or of oscillation? Oscillation it is called by a common figure of speech. The figure is so far correct, inasmuch as a person in doubt inclines now to one alternative and now to another. But does he will now the one, now the other? I think he does not will in the full sense of the term. For what is it fully and properly to will? I conceive the process to be this. A good is presented to the mind: a complacency is raised there by: the person adverts to his complacency, and so ac quiesces in it. Now, if I am not mistaken, an irreso lute person does not ordinarily accomplish a series of these processes in full. The advantages of one alterna tive strike him with a liking for it, but, as he looks inward, he does not approve of that liking; then come the rival advantages, and affect him in the same way, without his taking to them either. Thus he advances to the first stage of volition on this side and on that, but on neither side does he reach the second stage. I am not denying that he may reach it and then go back; but I say, so far as I can read my own consciousness on the matter, — and each man has no other conscious ness to read but his own, — that a man, when he hesi tates, does not usually accomplish in succession a num ber of complete conflicting volitions ; he does not usually make up his mind fully for a thing and then fully against JOHN LOCKE 87 it; but he does what the word hesitate signifies, he sticks fast halfway in the process of willing; and the thing which depends on his will is not done, simply because he never thoroughly wills it. If this be so, the facl is fatal to Locke's argumentation. The second argument is a restatement of the first. The first prosposition in it is true; the second is false, and the conclusion does not follow. In the third argument, again, the first proposition is true, and the second false, and so the conclusion fails. VI "To ask whether a man be at liberty to will motion or rest, speaking or silence, which he pleases, is to ask whether a man can will what he wills or be pleased with what he is pleased with, a question which I think needs no answer; and they who can make a question out of it must suppose one will to determine the acls of another, and another to determine that, and so on in infinitum" To suppose a man already to will or to be pleased with a thing, and then ask whether he can will it or be pleased with it, is of course absurd; but to say that no reason can be assigned for a man's freely willing a thing beyond his freely willing it, is, I believe, to speak the truth. Locke thinks that it involves an infinite series of wills. A man wills because he wills to will, and he wills to will because he wills to will to will, and so forth; but this is absurd; therefore, a man has no self- determination. In like manner it might be argued that we have no self-knowledge; because, if we had, we 88 FREE WILL should say, we know that we know, to infinity. Car dinal Newman remarks on this point: "Of course these reflex acts may be repeated in a series. As I pronounce that ' Great Britain is an island,' and then pronounce 'That "Great Britain is an island" has a claim on my assent,' or is to 'be assented to,' or to be 'accepted as true,' or to be 'believed,' or simply 'is true' (these predicates being equivalent), so I may proceed, 'The proposition "that Great Britain is an island is to be believed," is to be believed,' etc., etc., and so on to infinitum. But this would be trifling. The mind is like a double mirror, in which reflections of self within self multiply themselves till they are un- distinguishable, and the first reflection contains all the rest."* When an offer is made to an antiquarian of a trip to Constantinople, and he is delighted with the idea, that delight does not originate there and then with him. It is the result of the words addressed to him working upon his previous dispositions. The only way in which he personally has promoted the delight which he feels is by those his previous acts which have disposed him that way. But during that first instant of surprise and pleasure he is quite passive. And yet the volition to visit the city of Constan- tine is already drawn up, like a document awaiting his signature; or to use a more appropriate compari son, it lives already within him, and expects his recog nition and acknowledgement of it for his own. Sup pose that when he looks into himself he approves of * Grammar of Assent, p. 1 88. JOHN LOCKE 89 the complacency which he finds there, and fully and freely wills to undertake the journey, I ask what moves him to that free volition? And the answer is twofold, partly regarding the volition and partly the freedom of it. The volition, by which I mean here the original complacency taken in the idea of actually going to Constantinople, is, as I have said, the result of an impression from without encountering certain previous habits of mind in him who receives it. Thus far the motion comes from without, and not from the person's own self. But the freedom of the volition, — that is, the fact of the complacency being persevered in after advertence, when it might have been rejected, that perseverance is of the proper motion of the per son and proceeds from him, and from none other besides him. If you raise the question why he perse veres, you are liable to the demand, why should he not? The complacency has possession of his mind, and we know whence it came. To acquiesce in it and con sciously to sustain and intensify it, now that it is pre sent, is not to turn the act in a new direction, but to stamp it with a new character, and, as it were, to set the seal of the ego upon it. Clearly, therefore, the person can acquiesce in that complacency. It is no less clear that he need not acquiesce therein. For no na ture need acquiesce in what does not fully satisfy its needs. But the needs of man's nature rise as high as does his conception of good; and he conceives good far higher than going to Constantinople. That good, therefore, does not necessitate him to acquiesce in the cmoplaccncy which it excites within him. If he 90 FREE WILL withholds acquiescence, the complacency, being ad verted to without being approved, withers away. Once more I have explained what I believe to be the process of free volition. The account is open to criticism, as all accounts of delicate workings are. But I do not see how the reproach of postulating an infinite series of wills can be fastened upon it by a candid reader. VII *"Good and evil, present and absent, 'tis true, work upon the mind; but that which immediately deter mines the will from time to time to every voluntary action is the uneasiness of desire fixed on some absent good, either negative, as indolency to one in pain; or positive, as enjoyment of pleasure. That it is this un easiness that determines the will to the successive voluntary actions whereof the greatest part of our lives is made up, and by which we are conducted through different courses to different ends, I shall endeavour to show both from experience and the reason of the the thing. When a man is perfectly content with the state he is in, which is when he is perfectly without any uneasiness, what industry, what action, what will is there left but to continue in it? Of this every man's observation will satisfy him. . . Convince a man never so much that plenty has its advantages over poverty, make him see and own that the handsome conveni ences of life are better than nasty penury, yet as long as he is content with the latter and finds no uneasiness in it, he moves not; his will never is determined to any action that shall bring him out of it. Let a man be ever so well persuaded of the advantages of vir- * In this quotation the several passages stand not exadlly in the same order in which Locke presents them. JOHN LOCKE 91 tue, that it is as necessary to a man who has any great aims in this world, or hopes in the next, as food to life; yet till he hungers and thirsts after righteousness, till he feels an uneasiness in the want of it, his will will not be determined to any aclion in pursuit of this confessed greater good; but any other uneasiness he feels in himself shall take place and carry his will to other adions. . . If we inquire into the reason of what experience makes so evident in fact, and examine why 'tis uneasiness alone operates on the will and deter mines it in its choice, we shall find that, we being capable but of one determination of the will to one action at once, the present uneasiness that we are under does naturally determine the will, in order to that happiness which we all aim at in all our actions; forasmuch as whilst we are under any uneasiness we cannot apprehend ourselves happy or in the way to it; pain and uneasiness being by every one concluded and felt to be inconsistent with happiness, spoiling the relish even of those good things which we have, a little pain serving to mar all the pleasure we rejoiced in. And therefore that which of course determines the choice of our wills to the next action will always be the removing of pain, as long as we have any left, as the first and necessary step towards happiness. Another reason why 'tis uneasiness alone determines the will may be this: because that alone is present, and 'tis against the nature of things that what is absent should operate where it is not. It may be said that absent good may by contemplation be brought home to the mind and made present. The idea of it, indeed, may be in the mind, and viewed as present there; but nothing will be in the mind as a present good able to counterbalance the removal of any uneasiness which we are under till it raises our desire, and the uneasi- 92 FREE WILL ness of that has the prevalency in determining the will. Till then, the idea in the mind of whatever good is only there like other ideas, the object of bare, in- aclive speculation, but operates not on the will, nor sets us on work. . . For the removal of the pains we feel and are at present pressed with being the getting out of misery, and consequently the first thing to be done in order to happiness; absent good, though thought on, confessed and appearing to be good, not making any part of this unhappiness in its absence, is jostled out to make way for the removal of those uneasinesses we feel, till due and repeated contempla tion has brought it nearer to our mind, given some relish of it, and raised in us some desire, which then beginning to make a part of our present uneasiness stands upon fair terms with the rest to be satisfied, and so according to its greatness and pressure comes in its turn to determine the will. . . Were the will determined by the views of good, as it appears in contemplation greater or less to the understanding, which is the state of all absent good, and that which in the received opi nion the will is supposed to move to and to be moved by, I do not see how it could ever get loose from the infinite eternal joys of heaven, once proposed and con sidered as possible. . . This I think anyone may ob serve in himself and others, that the greater visible good does not always raise men's desires in proportion to the greatness it appears and is acknowledged to have, though every little trouble moves us, and sets us at work to get rid of it.. The reason whereof is evident from the nature of our happiness and misery itself. All present pain, whatever it be, makes a part of our present misery; but all absent good does not at any time make a part of our present happiness, nor the absence of it make a part of our misery. If it did, we JOHN LOCKE 93 should be constantly and infinitely miserable, there being infinite degrees of happiness which are not in our possession. All uneasiness, therefore, being re moved, a moderate portion of goo'1 serves at present to content men, and some few degrees of pleasure in a succession of ordinary enjoyments make up a hap piness wherein they can be satisfied. . . But we being in this world beset with sundry uneasinesses, dis tracted with different desires, the next inquiry natu rally will be, which of them has the precedency in de termining the will to the next action. And to that the answer is, that ordinarily which is the most pressing of those that are judged capable of being then removed. For the will, being the power of directing our opera tive faculties to some action for some end, cannot at any time be moved towards what is judged at that time unattainable. That would be to suppose an intelligent being designedly to act for an end only to lose its la bour; for so it is to act for what is judged not attain able, and therefore very great uneasinesses move not the will when they are j udged not capable of a cure : they in that case put us not upon endeavours. But these set apart, the most important and urgent uneasiness we at that time feel is that which ordinarily determines the will successively in that train of voluntary actions which make up our lives. The greatest present un easiness is the spur to action that is constantly felt and for the most part determines the will in its choice of the next action." Locke says 'that the will is determined ordinarily and for the most part by the greatest present uneasi ness: he does not say always. Indeed in the next section he sets a limitation to the axiom. With that limitation I shall have to deal. My argument here is 94 FREE WILL not directed against the position upon which Locke ultimately retires, but against the bare, unqualified statement that the will is ever and always determined by the greatest present uneasiness. And first let us take the word determined literally, in the full Hobbesian sense of necessitated. Man would be a pitiful creature if he were thus the puppet of his discomforts, the sport of the first uneasiness that be fell him. From the cradle to the grave he would grovel in unredeemed bondage to his bodily wants. The cra vings of appetite are our earliest promptings to action; and throughout life they touch us closest, and affect us most urgently in the way of present uneasiness. What room does such a doctrine leave for any forma tion of habits of temperance and self-control? I wonder what was the greatest present uneasiness of the martyr St Lawrence on his gridiron. His libe ration rested with himself: it was to be bought with a word. There was the pain of future remorse in the scale against that word of apostasy: there was the pain of actual burning fire making for it. Which was the greater pain? Some may argue from the martyr's choice, that he found the remorse more painful. But it is not a question of the agony of remorse against the agony of burning, but of a prospect of the former agony against an actual endurance of the latter. It is hard to believe that the shadow of threatened re morse distressed the young deacon more than did the reality of present fire. It is a revolting philosophy which pictures a witness of CHRIST unto torments and death, as merely doing after all the pleasantest thing that he JOHN LOCKE 95 could do under the circumstances, seeking his greater ease and comfort in the jaws of the flames, and only not denying his LORD because on the whole it was less painful to confess Him. It is not creditable to natu ral manliness, let alone to supernatural sanctity, to be driven by the prickings of uneasiness, as it were at the bayonet's point, to deeds of heroism and high renown. Or, taking the word determined in a looser sense, shall we say that the greatest present uneasiness is ever for the time being the strongest determinant, or mo tive, to the will, whether the will consent to it or not? That would be to ignore the well-established Aristo telian distinction between pleasures that presuppose a previous uneasiness, now being allayed, and plea sures that are attractive of themselves, no uneasiness being presupposed. These are Aristotle's words: They say that pain is a falling below the natural level, and pleasure a filling up to the natural level. But these are bodily incidents. If pleasure is a filling up to the natural level, the subject of pleasure will be that subject in which the filling up takes place, namely, the body. But that conclusion is not acceptable. Pleasure then is not a filling up, but the man feels pleasure when the filling up takes place. This belief seems to have arisen from the consideration of the pleasures and pains connected with nutrition; seeing that when men are in want of food, and have experienced the previousannoyance of hunger and thirst, then they feel pleasure in the making up of the deficiency. But this is not the case in all pleasures. The plea sures of mathematical discovery involve no such previous pain; nor the pleasures of the senses of smell, hearing and sight; nor the pleasures of memory and hope. It is not to allay any personal discomfort, or mental uneasiness, that the astronomer sweeps the heavens 96 FREE WILL with his spectroscope and speculates on the composi tion of the stars. Or does the poet sing to allay the turmoil ofa frenzied mind ? Keble, I know, maintains the affirmative in his once-celebrated Pr£T, to virtue or to vice, as St Paul tells the Romans, "Know ye not that to whomsoever ye yield yourselves servants to obey, his servants ye are whom ye obey; whether it be of sin unto death, or ot obe dience unto righteousness? . . . Being made free from sin, ye were made servants to righteousness. . . When * An ape. io6 FREE WILL ye were servants of sin, ye were free in regard to righteousness."* Free will is not given to us to romp and play the fool with, but to choose good, and there by contract that habit of choosing good which is called virtue. A person who should strive to observe neu trality between virtue and vice, and seek of set pur pose to escape entanglement with either in order to preserve his freedom intact, would speedily become the bondslave of vice. For performances always fall short of the ideal standard of good contemplated by the agent. If then the ideal in view be not too much of goodness^ the result actually achieved is likely to turn out a deal too much of 'villainy. Plato compared the ser vant of righteousness, the servant of unrighteousness, and the trimmer between the two, to the city of good government, the city of bad government, and the city of no government, respectively. He shows how rapidly the third state passes into the second, from no govern ment to bad government, from anarchy to tyranny. The man of no habits and no character degenerates into a man of bad character and vicious habits. I have no quarrel with Locke here. X "Liberty, 'tis plain, consists in a power to do or not to do, to do or forbear doing, as we will. This cannot be denied. But this seeming to comprehend only the actions of a man consecutive to volition, it is further inquired whether hebe at liberty towillor no. Andto this it has been answered that in most cases a man is not at liberty to forbear the act of volition; he must exert an * Romans vi, 16, 18, 20. JOHN LOCKE 107 act of his will, whereby the action proposed is made to exist or not to exist. But yet there is a case wherein a man is at liberty in respect of willing, and that is the choosing of a remote good as an end to be pursued. Here a man may suspend the act of his choice from being deter mined for or against the thing proposed, till he has examined whether it be really of a nature in itself and consequences to make him happy or no. . . That which in the train of our voluntary actions determines the will to any change of operation, is some present uneasiness, which is, or at least is always acccompanied with, that of desire. Desire is always moved by evil, to fly it; because a total freedom from pain always makes a necessary part of our happiness. But every good, nay, every greater good, does not constantly move desire, because it may not make, or may not be taken to make, any necessary part of our happiness. For all that we desire is only to be happy. But though this general desire of happiness operates constantly and invariably, yet the satisfaction of any particular desire can be su- pended from determining the will to any subservient action till we have maturely examined whether the parti cular apparent good, which we then desire, makes a part of our real happiness, or be consistent or inconsistent with it. The result of our judgement upon that examina tion is what ultimately determines the man, who could not be free, if his will were determined by anything but his own desire, guided by his own judgement." These two extracts together form a sort of map of the ground over which Locke has gone and I after him. Let us recapitulate results. Locke's first position was that "he is free who can do what he wills to do." Liberty, taken this way, is one with power. That man is the most free who is the strongest, the ablest, the io8 FREE WILL best supplied with means for effecting his purpose, whatever it be. An absolute sovereign, then, a Sesostris or a Bajazet, would show forth in his person the per fect type of a free man. The plenitude of liberty is the plenitude of arbitrary power; and Hobbes was right in his sarcastic observation, that when men cry for liberty, they want power. I am surprised at a patriarch of English Liberalism lending any countenance to this view. What fault had Locke to find with Charles II and James II, if those aspirants to autocracy were merely coveting for themselves that which is the birth right of every Englishman? Why did Locke place the German Ocean between him and two such liberty- loving English monarchs? Was it because they loved power too well? But if power is freedom, what Liberal can love it too well? I will desist, however, from this argumentum ad hominem. I need do no more than re mark that power may well be physical freedom, but it is not that mental and moral autonomy which a psycho logist, to say nothing of a statesman, is bound to study. Locke's second position was that " the will is de termined by the greatest present uneasiness." If that were true without qualification, there would be no room for the moral autonomy of free will. Uneasiness comes upon us from without. It is not ourselves, but our surroundings, including the accidents of our body independent of our will, that make us uneasy. Virtue, or the steady doing of what is right, could never be secured by these fortuitous promptings of uneasiness. Happily, most men are virtuous to a greater or less JOHN LOCKE 109 degree. They could not live within the pale of a civi lised community otherwise. Locke recognises this truth; and thereupon endows us with a power to " suspend the satisfaction of any particular desire till we have further considered whether the particular apparent good, which we then desire, makes a part of our real happiness." This third position is a near approximation to what I consider to be the true theory of free will. The one thing that I dislike about it is that Locke takes this suspension to be always itself an act of volition. Were it so, it would be necessary for the philosopher to inquire into the motive of that act of suspension, or the present * uneasiness ' that deter mined such act. It would look very much like a reso lution taken, a volition achieved, against the greatest present uneasiness. This troublesome inquiry is ren dered unnecessary, if we allow that the suspension or adjournment of action need not come of a positive volition to adjourn, but merely out of a negation, the absence of a full self-determination to act. The present * uneasiness,' as Locke calls it, determines the sponta neous complacency; but that motus primo primus^ as divines call it, is not an achieved volition; it must be adverted to, and under advertence its drawbacks must appear. Then, without further act, the adverting mind may hesitate to endorse and approve the complacency, and the complacency never becomes a volition till it is approved. To hurry the agent on so fast as to leave no time for advertence or consideration at all, would be to exclude free choice by the exclusion of all choice and full volition. Under the above explanation I i io FREE WILL agree with Locke that " the man could not be free, if his will were determined by anything else than his own desire, guided by his own judgement." In conclusion, I observe that it is one thing for an action to be our own by being freely done by us, and another thing for it to be our own by being an action becoming for us to do. An action becoming us may even be somewhat of a necessity on our part. I allude not to the outward constraint of any secular arm, but to the inner efficacy of a virtuous custom. A man who has long studied good and done good, sees evil so clearly to be evil that the horror of evil is the strongest repulsion of his nature. It is not too much to say that he cannot abruptly throw himself into the lap of wickedness. But this inability is not a privation of freedom in any sense in which freedom is valuable. Freedom is naught, ex cept it be riddance of something bad. To be rid of an indifferent thing is no gain: to be rid of a good thing is a loss. Deliver us from evil is the prayer which we are taught to offer for freedom. The evil that haunts the region of the intellect is ignorance, uncertainty and error. A free mind, then, is a mind endowed with a sure knowledge of truth. In one way such a mind is not free: it is restrained from doubt and delusion: it has surrendered to evi dence, and evidence holds it captive. In the region of the will dwells the evil of folly. From that the wise man is delivered in so far as he has compassed wisdom. The wiser he grows, the more nearly impossible it be comes for him to do a foolish thing. The one right course to take in every perplexity shines luminously JOHN LOCKE in before him. So schooled are his eyes to discern the beauty of that light that he will not, and scarcely can, diverge into the fenny quagmires where the ignis fa- tuus gleams. Is not that a happy impotence, snatching his soul from death and his feet from stumbling? I'Yeedman now of truth and goodness, finds he aught to envy in the licentious rovings of the runaway slave? It is well, in conclusion, to remark that the blissful dependence of a believer upon truth, and of a just man upon righteousness, is not entered upon without free ads of the will. He alone holds any high practi cal truth securely who has grasped it resolutely. He alone has any sort of gulf fixed in this world between his will and sin, who in many a circumstance of temp tation has had the power to transgress, and has not transgressed, and the power to do evil and has not done it. DAVID HUME DAVID HUME An Inquiry concerning Human Understanding Section VIII. Of Liberty and Necessity I M this circumstance alone that a controversy has been long kept on foot, and remains still un decided, we may presume that there is some ambi guity in the expression, and that the disputants affix different ideas to the terms employed in the contro versy. . . This has been the case in the long disputed question concerning liberty and necessity. . . I hope, therefore, to make it appear that all men have ever agreed in the doctrine both of necessity and of liberty, according to any reasonable sense which can be put on those terms; and that the whole controversy has turned hitherto upon words." We hear in this passage the echo of Locke's vehe ment denunciation of words ill understood, as the sources whence most disputes in philosophy spring. But there is yet another fountain-head, whence con tention issues in still greater volume. Many differ ences amongst philosophers are traceable to words ill understood, but many more to different aims in life chosen and pursued. For philosophy is not a bare speculation; it involves practice. From philosophy are derived the laws of conduct. The freedom of the will, if free it be, is a pragmatic consideration for us all. It is a summons to responsi- n6 FREE WILL bility, to merit or demerit, to exertion, to fighting, to victory or defeat. It means that we are not embarked as otiose passengers, but we must work our passage through life, and we shall drift to shipwreck if we will not work. Though the LORD is our light and our sal vation, we need to follow the light in order to attain salvation. When we have wilfully loved darkness and gone astray, the hope of reaching our destined end dies down in our breasts; we become uneasy and repine at our misconduct, which is exactly the frame of mind wherein a man would gladly hear that there is no free will, and consequently no ground for remorse, no sin. Let the advocates of necessarianism consider what a source of prejudice is here arrayed on their side. Then they will be less hasty in giving judgement that con sciousness does not witness to freedom, and that, apart from misunderstandings of language, all mankind are necessarians. Qui bono fait? Whose interest is it to figure as one necessitated in all his actions ? To form a rough guess whether a contradiction be tween two philosophers is real or verbal, it is well to look whether the two men agree in their practice. If they do, there is reason to hope that their specula tions are not really at variance, and that they might be brought to manifest harmony by mutual explanation and definition of terms. But where one disputant takes one line of action, and his opponent acts just the re verse way, there is indication of a conflict of thought, which may be aggravated rather than appeased by a removal of ambiguity of expression. DAVID HUME 117 II "It seems evident that if all the scenes of nature were continually shifted in such a manner that no two events bore any resemblance to each other, but every object was entirely new, without any similitude to what ever had been seen before, we should never in that case have attained the least idea of necessity, or of a con nexion among these objects. We might say, upon such a supposition, that one object or event has followed another; not that one was produced by another. The relation of cause and effect must be utterly unknown to mankind. Inference and reasoning concerning the operations of nature would from that moment be at an end; and the memory and senses remain the only channels by which the knowledge of any real existence could possibly have access to the mind. Our idea there fore of necessity and causation arises entirely from the uniformity observable in the operations of nature, where similar objects are constantly conjoined together, and the mind is determined by custom to infer the one from the appearance of the other. These two circum stances form the whole of that necessity which we ascribe to matter. Beyond the constant conjunction of similar objects, and the consequent inference from one to the other, we have no notion of any necessity or connexion. If it appear, therefore, that all mankind have ever al lowed, without any doubt or hesitation, that these two circumstances take place in the voluntary actions of men and in the operations of mind, it must follow that all mankind have ever agreed in the doctrine of necessity, and that they have hitherto disputed merely for not understanding each other." However irregularly the scenes nf nature were shit- n8 FREE WILL ted, still I think we should not fail to attain some idea of Jiecjsssitvj nay, I am not sure that the idea would not be imprinted upon us even more vividly than it is now. Suppose that, when a man rose in the morn ing, the floor of his bedroom at first felt like thistles and cut his feet: the moment after it was like smooth glass: then it became a bog, and then a snowfield: sup pose that the water with which he tried to wash turned to ink, and then to treacle, and then to oil of vitriol; that the soap burnt his skin and then gilt it; that his stature grew and shrank through all sizes between three feet and thirty; that he took by turns the shape of every animal in the Zoological Gardens; and that changes like these befell him all the days of his life without any regularity of recurrence; still, I am apt to reckon, if he preserved his personal identity, and remained conscious to himself of an enduring self or ego, he might attain an idea of necessity, clear and distinct to a degree. For he would live under per petual constraint. Nature is a stubborn thing for any of us to deal with. Yet we know something of her ways and observances, and can arrange our plans according to them. The man I am supposing would desire and contrive as we do, but, with the protean instruments supplied to his hands, he would be for ever failing of his purpose. Then he would understand what " I can not " meant. And what else is it to say, " I cannot," but to say, "Necessity is upon me"? "1 cannot speak," that is, "I am under a necessity of silence"; "I can not help it," that is, " I needs must suffer it." We feel the pressure of necessity when we realise the limita- DAVID HUME 119 tion of our being and ability. Now what would a man find himself able to do in a universe where law reigned not ? When he hit upon an action that suited his pur pose, he would try it again, but the same means might not serve him another time. Then he would desire, and desire in vain : so necessity would make herself felt upon him. Who so necessitous as the impotent ? The state of chaotic irregularity, which we imagined for example's sake, was taken by Plato and his followers to have been the actual state of the universe of matter, before the supreme mind subjected it to law and uni formity. "In those days," says Plato, "nothing had any order except by accident, nor did anything at all deserve to bear any of the names that now are used, such zsfire, water, and the names of the other elements. All this chaos the Artificer first sorted out and made into a cosmos, and then out of it He constituted the present universe."* And again: "God, finding the whole visible universe not at rest, but moving in an unharmonious and disorderly manner, reduced it from disorder to order." f Now the name which the Plato- nists gave to the primitive principle of capriciousness, irregularity, inconstancy, and variation in nature, was this very name of ava-y/o/, or necessity. Once more the great founder of the school: "The universe is a com pound, the result of a union of necessity and mind. . . We must distinguish two sorts of causes, the one necessary and the other divine."J It is usual to iden tify freedom with caprice, and necessity with uni formity. But a little consideration will show the reason * Plato, Timaui, 69. t Id. ib. 30. \ Id. ib. 48, 68. 120 FREE WILL that there was on Plato's side. It is essential to free will that two men in the same situation should not inevi tably make the same choice. Yet if both are equally wise, and both choose for the best, they will in point of fad often choose the same; for frequently there is one best course evident to intelligence. Plato supposed that nature was uniform, in so far as it was swayed by the divine Mind for the best. On the other hand, where there is no mind and no appreciation of good ness, things will fall out blindly, capriciously, irregu larly, or, as the Platonist said, by force of necessity, by brute force, the vis consili expcrs of Horace. The Greeks called that "necessity" against which human contrivance was powerless. Now if nature were not anywhere uniform, human contrivance would be powerless everywhere. We might then have an idea of necessity, even though nature were not uniform. But nature is uni form. Is then Hume right in saying that "our idea of necessity and causation arises entirely from the uni formity observable in the operations of nature"? What is our idea of necessity, according to Sume? He assigns two notes to that idea, "the constant con junction of similar objects and the consequent infe rence from one to the other." Uniform conjunction prompting inference makes necessity, says Hume. Happily for mankind, Hume is wrong. Happily for mankind, I say: for were this analysis correct, it would be a bar to all progress in the arts of life, and to all amelioration of man's life on earth consequent upon such progress. Let us consider for example the pro- DAVID HUME 121 gress of surgery. Fifty years ago certain injuries were uniformly conjoined with death, and death might be inferred from the receiving of such injuries. If sur geons had been guided by Hume, they would have acquiesced in the necessity of death in such cases; they would have avowed the impossibility of cure, and, says Aristotle, "When the impossible is come upon, men desist."* But enterprising and inventive men took another course. "True," they said, "in the past people always have died of these injuries, but that is no reason why they always should die: what always has been, need not be: past uniformity does not make necessity." They tried new conditions, novel treatment, extra precautions, and patients recovered. The necessary then is not what always has been, but what in the na ture of things must be: Necessity is not constant conjunction, but implication. ''"For a l'On|UflftiOfi flm,flways is, belongs to the actual order of fact; but a conjunction that must be, appertains to the ideal order of possibility.^ and B may ever coexist, as rue earth ana moon coexist, and yet the idea of one does not include the idea of the other: they may be separated in thought, though in fact they will not be separated: their separation is an intelligible hypothesis. On the other hand, were A and B necessarily connected, the having them apart would be a contradiction in terms: A without B would not be A, and B without A would not be B, the one supposing the other. No conceivable arrangement then could separate the two. * Etb. Nic. i. 122 FREE WILL Such is the necessary connexion between a natural effect and the causes that lead to it. When any material agent acts, the action absolutely must be as it is. Not only does the moon always draw after it the tidal wave, it cannot do otherwise than draw it. For the moon and the earth to be as they are without interference, and yet for there to be no tide, is an hypothesis that can not be expressed without simultaneous assertion and denial of the nature of the two bodies. As the hypo thesis is self-contradictory, so is the thing absolutely impossible. Of course an arrangementmight be devised to prevent the tides, but that would not be the present arrangement. GOD Himself, if He wished the tide not to rise, would not leave things exactly as they are, without altering or adding to the forces now in opera tion. As things stand, supposing no change in their position, and no new force, natural or preternatural, brought to bear, the tide must rise, it cannot but rise, it rises not only invariably and uniformly, but of a necessity. By { necessary ' therefore I understand that which can not but be. I proceed to examine whence this notion is derived. It is not gathered from the study of external nature alone, for, as Hume strongly urges, the utmost which that study directly and by itself teaches is that which always is. If all our knowledge was got by look ing outside of ourselves, I doubt whether we should have any idea of necessity, or of active causation, or even of being. Hume in this argumentation tacitly assumes that our knowledge is entirely procured by looking outwards. On the unsound support of that DAVID HUME 123 assumption the whole weight of his reasoning rests. Let me repeat his words. He says that if nature were not uniform, "inference and reasoning concerning the operations of nature would from that moment be at an end, and the memory and senses remain the only channels by which the knowledge of any real exis tence could possibly have access to the mind." Whence I gather that under present conditions, where nature is uniform, the only channels by which the knowledge of any real existence can possibly have access to the mind are the senses, the memory, and inferences and reasoning concerning the operations of nature. The senses, I presume, convey to us impressions of what is outside of us, the memory reinstates those impressions, and the reason sorts and arranges them, like with like. Meanwhile, what is become of ourselves ? Have we no knowledge of ourselves? or is self-con sciousness a sensation, — of what sense? Do we see or hear or taste or smell self, or feel self with the sensory papill»jr, which Plato supposes to be the instant of transition from rest to motion, or from motion to rest.* Hume may open all his batteries upon this position without touching one single defender of free will. We all allow that character has a vast influence on conduct: we only deny that it has an absolutely determining influence upon every single point of premeditated action. Like wise we allow that acts form habits; and character is a sum total of acquired habits and congenital proclivities. Character is more or less permanent; but there is something still more permanent than character: that is the " person, or creature endowed with thought and consciousness," a definition which I thankfully take from Hume. Free will in act is eminently a personal act: it is the rational creature's outpouring of its own vitality; and where the act is evil and vitality is poured out with will and deliberation upon an undue object, the person thereby becomes a more or less wicked person, and so remains until the act is revoked. A wicked character is a mark of wicked deeds: it is produced by them and reproduces them in turn. The deeds by which such a character is produced are freely done. The deeds which it produces are free less and less as they are multiplied, and as the evil character of the doer is more and more confirmed. A wicked cha racter then is a sure mark of wicked deeds having * Plato, Tarmenictts, i 5 6d. DAVID HUME 159 gone before, and a probable mark of more to follow. Wicked deeds are a sure mark of a wicked character bcinij .it le;ist in course of formation, but not neces sarily already formed, a fact which founds the Aristo telian distinction between UK par fa and afcoXoaroc.* Volition, like muscular and nervous energy, with which in man it is essentially connected, tends to run in grooves according as it is exercised. There is no thing incompatible with free will there. Free will is limited, like everything else in man. XI " If voluntary actions be subjected to the same laws of necessity with the operations of matter, there is a continued chain of necessary causes preordained and predetermined, reaching from the original cause of all to every single volition of every human creature; no contingency any where in the universe; no indifference, no liberty. While we act, we are at the same time acted upon. The ultimate Author of all our volitions is the Creator of the world, who first bestowed motion on this immense machine and placed all beings in that particular position whence every subsequent event by an inevitable necessity must result. Human actions, therefore, either can have no moral turpitude at all, as proceeding from so good a cause; or if they have any turpitude, they must involve our Creator in the same guilt, while He is acknowledged to be their ulti mate cause and author. For as a man who fired a mine is answerable for all the consequences whether the train he employed be long or short, so wherever a con tinued chain of necessary causes is fixed, that Being, * See Nicomackean Ethics, vii, 9, or Aquinas Etkum, vol. i> pp. 170, 171. i6o FREE WILL either finite or infinite, who produces the first is like wise the author of all the rest, and must both bear the blame and acquire the praise which belongs to them. Our clear and unalterable ideas of morality establish this rule upon unquestionable reasons when we exa mine the consequences of any human action, and these reasons must still have greater force when applied to the volitions and intentions of a Being infinitely wise and powerful. Ignorance or impotence may be pleaded for so limited a creature as man; but those imperfec tions have no place in our Creator. He foresaw, He ordained, He intended all those actions of men which we so rashly pronounce criminal. And we must there fore conclude either that they are not criminal or that the Deity, not man, is accountable for them. But as either of these positions is absurd and impious, it follows that the doctrine from which they are deduced cannot possibly be true." This is an objection which Hume urges against himself with a vivacity and force that deserve the best thanks of his opponents. In answer he avows that the difficulty is not to be got over by accepting the first alternative, the position that no human actions are criminal. He finds it as impossible to deny wickedness as to deny pain and ugliness in this world of woe. He says: "Why should not the acknowledgement of a real distinction between vice and virtue be reconcilable to all speculative systems of philosophy as well as that of a real distinction between personal beauty and de formity? Both these distinctions are founded in the natural sentiments of the human mind, and these sentiments are not to be controlled or altered by any philosophical theory or speculation whatsoever." DAVID HUME 161 As Hume does not deny the criminality of certain human actions while he affirms the necessity of them, one is curious to see by what shift he escapes the second horn of his own dilemma. How ever does he avoid the "absurd and impious position," for so he calls it, of charging the Judge of all the earth with all the wrong done there ? He makes his escape in the fol lowing characteristic manner: "The second objection admits not of so easy and satisfactory an answer; nor is it possible to explain dis tinctly how the Deity can be the mediate cause of all the actions of men, without being the author of sin and moral turpitude. These are mysteries, which mere natural and unassisted reason is very unfit to handle; and whatever system she embraces, she must find her self involved in inexplicable difficulties, and even con tradictions, at every step which she takes with regard to such subjects. To reconcile the indifference and con tingency of human actions with prescience; or to de fend absolute decrees, and yet free the Deity from being the author of sin, has been found hitherto to exceed all the power of philosophy. Happy, if she be thence sensible of her temerity, when she pries into these sublime mysteries; and leaving a scene so full of obscurities and perplexities, return with suitable modesty to her true and proper province, the exami nation of common life; where she will find difficulties enow to employ her inquiries, without launching into so boundless an ocean of doubt, uncertainty and contradiction ! " There is a certain vulpine humility in all this. But it had been more honest either to admit the objection 1 62 FREE WILL as valid and unanswerable,an admission tantamount to a denial of GOD, — for a bad god is no god at all ; or else to repudiate that Humian doctrine from which the whole objection proceeds, that "voluntary actions be subjected to the same laws of necessity with the operations of matter." JOHN STUART MILL JOHN STUART MILL Logic, Boo{ VI, Chap. II. Of Liberty and Necessity. Examination of Sir William Hamilton s Philo sophy, Chap. XXVI. On the Freedom of the Will I "CORRECTLY conceived, the doctrine called \^4 Philosophical Necessity is simply this: that, given the motives which are present to an individual's mind, and given, likewise, the character and disposi tion of the individual, the manner in which he will act may be unerringly inferred; that if we knew the person thoroughly, and knew all the inducements which are acting upon him, we could foretell his con duct with as much certainty as we can predict any physical event. This proposition 1 take to be a mere interpretation of universal experience, a statement in words of what every one is internally convinced of. No one who believed that he knew thoroughly the cir cumstances of any case, and the characters of the dif ferent persons concerned, would hesitate to foretell how all of them would act. Whatever degree of doubt he may in fact feel arises from the uncertainty whether he really knows the circumstances, or the character of some one or other of the persons, with the degree of accuracy required; but by no means from thinking that if he did know these things, there could be any uncertainty what the conduct will be." 1 66 FREE WILL Mill strives to rest his doctrine, which is one with that of Hume, upon experience. But I observe that the experience which he invokes is not any know ledge of fact, but a belief about an unobserved con tingency: it is not an experience of what is, but an expectation of what would be in a certain issue which never occurs. No one ever does know any person thoroughly, nor the relative values of all the motives affecting any person's conduct out upon a new field of choice where he has never been tried before, where he cannot proceed by force of habit, where he will have to make up his mind afresh, — the very situation in which, if anywhere, free will must come into play. Even a successful prediction in such a case would prove nothing. The success might be due, three- quarters to shrewdness and the remaining quarter to luck, as when one has backed the winner of the Derby. "Three-quarters to shrewdness," I say, for I admit that a free volition may be predicted with probability. 1 deny only that it can be predicted with certainty even under the fullest knowledge of antecedent conditions of choice. Not with certainty, because the volition is not essentially contained in those conditions. Against this position Mill alleges "a mere interpretation of universal experience," — his interpretation, to wit, but certainly not his experience. As I have shown against Hume, the libertarian interpretation, properly guarded and explained, suits all experienced facts of predic tion as well as "the doctrine called Philosophical Necessity." Nothing, then, is thereby proved on cither side. JOHN STUART MILL 167 II "The religious metaphysicians who have asserted Lhc freedom of the will have always maintained it to be consistent with divine foreknowledge of our actions; and if with divine, then with any other foreknowledge." As religious metaphysicians we speak of" the GOD of the Theist and of the Christian ; a GOD who is numeri cally One, who is Personal; the Author, Sustainer and Finisher of all things, the Life of Law and Order, the Moral Governor; One who is Supreme and Sole; like Himself, unlike all things besides Himself, which are but His creatures; distinct from, independent of them all; One who is self-existing, absolutely infinite, who has ever been and ever will be, to whom nothing is past or future; who is all perfection, and the fullness and archetype of every possible excellence, the Truth Itself, Wisdom, Love, Justice, Holiness; One who is All- powerful, All-knowing, Omnipresent, Incomprehen sible."* I am not concerned with the correctness of this representation: my sole purpose is to show that they who believe it to be correct are not committed to the inference that if the freedom of the will is con sistent with the divine foreknowledge of our actions, it must be consistent likewise with any other fore knowledge. The foreknowledge ascribed to "the GOD of the Theist and of the Christian" not standing on a level with any other foreknowledge, Mill's argu ment a part becomes inadmissible. God is"One,who is self-existing, absolutely infinite, who has ever been and ever will be, to whom nothing is * Grammar of\fssfftf, p. 98. 1 68 FREE WILL past or future." He is the perfed realisation of all that can be, filling all bounds of being, filling all space and time, yesterday and to-day and for ever the same, stationary in the plentitude of being. Like His being, His knowledge is measured by eternity; it all exists together, it embraces all time. Whatever things come to be in time, are to God eternally present. His vision ranges from eternity over all things as they are under His unvarying all-pervading gaze. To us the past and the future, when we know them, are present in their images or in their signs.* But to God they are present in themselves, for they are in Him as in their first principle. We are placed at the * " If the future and the past are, I would know where they are. And if I cannot yet compass that, still I know that, wherever they are, they are not there future or past but present. For if there also they are future, they are not yet there; if there they are past, they are no longer there. Wherever, therefore, they are, and whatever they are, they are not save in the present. When the past is related truly, it is not the past things themselves that are produced from memory, but words formed from the images of them, like footprints which in passing by they have impressed on the mind through the senses. My boyhood for instance, which is no more, is in the time past, which is no more; but when I con over and tell my impression of it, I am looking at an objecl in the present time, because the im pression is still in my memory. . . When the future is said to be seen, it is not the things themselves which as yet are not, or which are future, — it is their causes or signs perchance, that are seen, which signs already are. . . It is now plain and clear that neither the future nor the past is. Nor is it properly said, There are three tenses, the present, the past, and the future; but perhaps it might properly be said: There are three tenses, the present of things past, the present of things present, and the present of things future. For these are three certain realities in the mind, and elsewhere I sec them not; the present of things past, which is memory; the present of things present, which is intuition; and the present of things future, which is expectation." — St Augustine's Confessions, xi, 18, 20. JOHN STUART MILL 169 circumference of the circle of which He is the centre. The instant in which we are is one now out of many: from the divine now all nows radiate, and it is equiva lent to them all. Thus to God there is no foreknow ledge or afterknowledge, but simply knowledge of the present. This knowledge, as applied to adual creation, receives in theology the name of the " science of vision." By it God sees, — He sees in the a6l itself, He does not calculate from antecedents, — all that He Himself is freely about to do, or rather is doing, in the way of creating, working miracles and the like, as also all the effects that will proceed from natural causes, whether from the necessary determination of their natures, or through the use made of them by free agents. God, looking at a creature, sees its history all at once before Him, albeit that, to the creature, the facls are evolved successively. The generation that shall be alive thirty- five years hence will behold what the ruler of France at that time does.* They will not calculate his actions from the motives, they will watch them being done. Thirty-five years hence is present in the now of God. He is a spectator of what is to go on then. This is marvellous doctrine. If it were not marvel lous, it would hardly be likely to be true of Him whose name is called Wonderful. But it is not on the mar- vellousness, nor even on the truth of the doclrine that I here wish to insist, but on the bare facl that this is the doctrine of those "religious metaphysicians" who assert the freedom of the will and maintain it to be consistent with the divine foreknowledgeofourcon- * Written about the year 1872. i?o FREE WILL duct. Such eternal foreknowledge is a thing without parallel in the human mind. It gives, therefore, no ground for the inference set up by Mill. Ill " It is not the doctrine that our volitions and actions are invariable consequents of our antecedent states of mind, that is either contradicted by our consciousness or felt to be degrading. But the doctrine of causation, when considered as obtaining between our volitions and their antecedents, is almost universally conceived as involving more than this. Many do not believe, and very few practically feel, that there is nothing in causa tion but in variable, certain and unconditional sequence. There are few to whom mere constancy of succession appears a sufficiently stringent bond of union for so peculiar relation as that of cause and effect. Even if the reason repudiates, the imagination retains the feeling of some more intimate connexion, of some peculiar tie or mysterious constraint exercised by the antecedent over the consequent. Now this it is which, considered as applying to the human will, conflicts with our con sciousness and revolts our feelings. We are certain that, in the case of our volitions, there is not this myster ious constraint. We know that we are not compelled, as by a magical spell, to obey any particular motive. Wre feel that if we wish to prove that we have the power of resisting the motive, we could do so (that wish being, it needs scarcely be observed, a new antecedent); and it would be humiliating to our pride and paralysing to our desire of excellence if we thought otherwise. But neither is any such mysterious compulsion now sup posed, by the best philosophical authorities, to be exer cised by any cause over its effect. Those who think that causes draw their effects after them by a mystical JOHN STUART MILL 171 tie, are right in believing that the relation between volitions and their antecedents is of another nature. But they should go further and admit that this is also true of all other effects and of their antecedents. If such a tie is considered to be involved in the word necessity, the doctrine is not true of human actions; but neither is it then true of inanimate objects. It would be more correct to say that matter is not bound by necessity than that mind is so." This language is, of course, no more than an echo of Hume (nn. 6, 7). But because it is striking and clear, and is caught up with approval by men of our time, and even by boys, it had better be listened to attentively and judged for what it is worth. Mill teaches that volition does not differ from mechanical action, so far as the invariable and unconditional se quence of consequents upon antecedents is concerned. Let the simultaneous facts, A, B, C, D, and others, be followed by the fact Z. Then, says Mill, whatever be the character of the facts, whether mental or phy sical, it is certain that wherever A, B, C and the rest go before, without addition or diminution, there Z will come after. Experience may show that Z occurs whether A precedes or not. Therefore A may be left out of the account, as likewise may other antecedents, as B, C, D, for the same reason. But it will be found that some antecedents, such as F and G, cannot be omitted without the result Z failing to appear. These antecedents must be retained. Again, the insertion of some new antecedents, as P, Q, R, may be found to prevent the appearance of Z, even though F and G, 172 FREE WILL and all others whose presence is indispensable, are duly there. The omission of these obstructive ante cedents must be bargained for. Let the indispensable antecedents, F, G, etc., be summed under the general expression E, and the impeding antecedents, P, Q, R, etc., under the general expression E. Then the expres sion E - E will stand for what Mill calls the cause of Z, Z being any fact either of mind or of matter. Let us take an illustration from each department. And first of matter. A smith takes a piece of iron, heats it red-hot in the forge, and beats it flat on the anvil. The iron becoming flat is a fact or phenomenon of matter. The antecedents to it are the smith's hav ing got up that morning, having had his breakfast, having work to do, having put the iron in the fire, having hammered it, — there are these and other ante cedents too numerous to mention. The result is that the iron gets flattened out. Any similar iron would get flattened out in similar circumstances. Even a varia tion of circumstances, up to a certain point, is compa tible with the attainment of the result. That smith, we will suppose, said his morning prayers. But iron will yield to beating, whether the hands that strike it have been previously clasped in prayer or not. GOD rains upon the just and the unjust. On the other hand, if the smith is stricken blind, his blow is likely to fail, and the metal will go unflattened. Thus some conditions are requisite to the effect, and some are superfluous. Further, there are conditions of which the absence is positively required. The hot bar must not be cooled in water, else the beating will make no JOHN STUART MILL 173 impression. When all the indispensable conditions are there, and the preventive conditions are all absent, the result, the flattening of the iron, will be brought to pass, — infallibly^ M ill would say : I should add, and necessarily. Let us pass to a phenomenon of will. A man has gained an importantsuccess,somethingthat he imagines will fix his name in history: he has vindicated his country's honour in the field, or amended her consti tution at home, or he has come forward in the ranks of her poets, her artists or her men of science: and as he thinks of his achievement, his heart is lifted up within him, as was the heart of Lucifer of old, taking the glory to himself away from GOD. If the person deliberately consents to this movement of vainglory, he commits a sin: so all moralists who recognise the rights of the Creator agree in teaching. If we are to believe Mill, the guilty consent there follows upon the temptation with a sequence as indefectible as the flattening of a hot iron consequent upon percussion. When a smith hammers a bar that has been properly heated, and when there is no interference, natural or supernatural, with the operation, it is incredible to Mill, as it is to every reasonable man, that the shape of the bar should remain unchanged. Suppose now two persons are placed together in the situation of trial which I have described. Their antecedent dis positions, their present motives, arising as well from nature as from grace, are essentially alike in number and in kind. In that case it is simply incredible to Mill that one man should sin and the other remain innocent. Crimes, he thinks, are ruled by the same i74 FREE WILL laws as landslips. One cliff will not stand in the exacl: situation in which a similar cliff has fallen: neither will Abel ever do right, if placed, with Cain's charac ter, in an occasion similar to that in which Cain has done wrong. Our author indeed says: "We know that we are not compelled, as by a magical spell, to obey any par ticular motive. We feel that if we wished to prove that we have the power of resisting the motive we could do so." That wish, he adds with emphasis, would be "a new antecedent." Just as well may it be said that a cliff is not compelled, by any magical spell or natural necessity, to give way under any particular mining operation. If, as you cut away the rock, you judiciously replace it with iron pillars, they will bear up the superincumbent mass as it stood before. Those pillars are new antecedents. Without them, or some support like them, the rock, being undermined, surely will fall. With them, if they are sufficient, it as surely will stand. So, on Mill's showing, a man in tempta tion surely will sin, unless it occurs to him that it would be a fine thing to show his power of resistance. Without that, or some deterring thought of that sort, his offence is calculable, with mathematical precision, from the occasion given him. But supply him with motive sufficient, — or if you like to speak theologically, with grace sufficient, — to keep him out of sin, and there is no more danger of his yielding to temptation than there is of his sinking through a stone pavement. We have here a system of necessarianism, rigid as that of any Calvinist divine. The recognition of anything JOHN STUART MILL 175 that possibly might be other than what actually is cannot stand with the doctrine of philosophical necessity, taught nowadays by "the best philosophical authorities," as Mill complacently styles himself and friends. The se quence of antecedent and consequent in this system is so close, so invariable, so uniform, as to leave no room anywhere for edging in a might be, A bridge has given way with a train upon it. It might not be that the train should not fall into the river. It might not be that the bridge, constructed as it was, should not give way under that pressure. It might not be that the railway officials, with their individual characters and incentives to action, should have had the forethought and energy to prevent the train from going upon the bridge. It might not be that the engineer of the bridge should have constructed it in any other way. It might not be that anything which has happened should have happened otherwise. Everywhere, event follows event with rigid calculable precision, till we come to the pri meval arrangement, the original collocation of mate rials in the universe. That, one is tempted to say, might have been arranged quite differently. But here those self-styled "best philosophical authorities" de clare human knowledge to stop short. Nothing, they tell us, can be known as to how the first position of things came about. Then it cannot be known that things might have been arranged in the beginning in any other fashion than as they actually were arranged. Consequently, so far as we know, all that happens is inevitable; what happens not, is impossible; andnothing might have been, or might be, except what has been, 1 76 FREE WILL is, or shall be. This is what the doctrine of philosophi cal necessity comes to, — Hobbism, pure and simple. A "mystical tie," indeed, would that relation be, of which there were no terms! The doctrine that "there is nothing in causation but invariable, certain and un conditional sequence," abolishes the terms of the re lation of cause and effect, and cuts the relation afloat to go by itself; this event before, and that event after, no permanent being anywhere. If there is nothing of permanent being in ourselves, and nothing permanent in nature, on what ground do we assert the perma nence of any law of nature? Why must the future re semble the past, if nothing of the past stands over into the future? No wonder if "many men do not believe, and very few practically feel," that there is nothing in the universe but a ghostly procession of phantoms going before and phantoms coming behind. No wonder if many men persist in looking for substantial realities, and for ties, "mystical" or otherwise, so long as they are real, that is to say, "real relations" between cause and effect. We divide these substantial realities into persons and things, — persons habitually conscious of self, things totally unconscious: dumb animals, who need not here be considered, come in between. A thing es sentially acts upon whatever comes within the range of its action, as the earth on the moon, the sun on the planets, every particle of matter upon every other par ticle to which its power extends. The effect of such action is some determination to motion. This action of things is called transient, because the term of action lies without the agent. Therefore are things called JOHN STUART MILL 177 inert ^ because they do not aft within or upon them selves, as it were setting themselves in motion. A pefsotijOn the other hand, — the only person I here speak of is thinking man, as such, — is impressed and acted upon by objects without entering into his ken, and to this impression there is a responsive action from within. This action is immanent, for it remains within the agent. This is the act of perceiving and liking, or disliking, and in its first stage this action is necessary, being determined, as determinists truly say, by envi ronment and character. It is only in a further stage, when the ego consciously awakes to judge of this spon taneous and necessary like or dislike, that the exercise of free will begins. Libertarians have this abiding dissatisfaction with Hume and Mill and the modern determinist school, that, as men blinded by physics to everything above the physical and material order, they ignore a vital difference between beings conscious of the ego and beings totally unconscious^ between persons in fact and things. Still, dissatisfied as we are, we are not surprised: we remember that we are dealing with men who have shut out from their philosophical purview all such con cepts as that of substantial, permanent Being and Per sonality (oufft'o, u7ro